Skip to main content
Log in

Legal ritual

  • Published:
Law and Critique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

References

  1. Lon Fuller, “Consideration and Form”,Columbia Law Review 45 (1945), 799, 800.

    Google Scholar 

  2. T. Arnold,Symbols of Government (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1935), 22. “When they do recognize a taboo, they condemn it, instead of realizing that such is the stuff which binds society together and makes it orderly and comfortable in its spirit.”

    Google Scholar 

  3. B. Malinowski,Crime and Custom in Savage Society (Totowa, N.J.: Littlefield, Adams & Co., 1926, 1982 ed.); M. Gluckman,Politics, Law and Ritual in Tribal Society (Chicago: Aldine, 1965), andThe Judicial Process Among the Barotse of Northern Rhodesia (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1955, rev. ed. 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  4. See, e.g., R. Pound,Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1922, 1954 ed.). Also see E. Durkheim, “The Nature and Evolution of Contract”, inDurkheim and the Law, ed. S. Lukes and A. Scull (New York: St. Martins Press, 1983), 199–200.

    Google Scholar 

  5. B. Nicholas,An Introduction to Roman Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1965), 61.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See, e.g., Mary Douglas,Purity and Danger: an Analysis of the Concepts of Pollution and Taboo (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1966, 1984 ed.), 61. Also see generally E. W. Said,Orientalism (New York: Vintage, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  7. E. A. Hoebel,The Law of Primitive Man (New York: Atheneum, 1974); Victor Turner,The Ritual Process (Chicago: Aldine, 1969), 8: “... certain regularities that emerged from the analysis of numerical data, such as village genealogies and censuses and records of succession to office and inheritance of property, became fully intelligible only in the light of values embodied and expressed in symbols at ritual performances.” Also see Sally F. Moore, “Legal Liability and Evolutionary Interpretation”, inLaw as Process (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), 83–134; L. Rosen, “Equity and Discretion in a Modern Islamic Legal System”,Law and Society Review 15 (1980–1981), 217–45.

    Google Scholar 

  8. But see Moore, “Introduction”,Law as Process, supra n.7, at 1–31. Also see C. Geertz, “Fact and Law in Comparative Perspective”, inLocal Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology (New York: Basic Books, 1983), 167–234.

    Google Scholar 

  9. J.M. Cullen, “Some Principles of Animal Communication”, inNon-Verbal Communication, ed. R.A. Hinde (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1972), 116.

    Google Scholar 

  10. M.D. Mather, “The Treatment of an Obsessive-Compulsive Patient by Discrimination Learning and Reinforcement of Decision-Making”,Behaviour Research and Therapy 8 (1970), 315–18.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See e.g., V. Turner,The Forest of Symbols: Aspects of Ndembu Ritual (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1967), 19; D. I. Kertzer,Ritual Politics and Power (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1988), 8; R. Firth,Elements of Social Organization (London: Watts, 1951), 222; E. M. Ahern,Chinese Ritual and Politics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Turner,supra n.11, at 10; Firth,supra n.11, at 222.

    Google Scholar 

  13. “Introduction”, inSecular Ritual, eds. S. F. Moore and B. G. Myerhoff (Assen, The Netherlands: Van Gorcum, 1977), 3.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid. “Introduction”, in

    Google Scholar 

  15. Douglas,supra n.6, at 58.

    Google Scholar 

  16. W. Robertson Smith,Lectures on the Religion of the Semites (London: S.A. Cook, 1927), 3rd ed., esp. lectures vi–xi.

    Google Scholar 

  17. R. Benedict, “Ritual”,Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences 13 (1937), 396–397. “The rite is similarly more stable and more fundamental than the rationalizations that universally accompany it. As soon as it receives traditional form the ritual itself becomes a standard of reference; ‘from it proceed the random whys, and to it return the indeterminate therefores.’”

    Google Scholar 

  18. C. Geertz, “Religion As a Cultural System”, inThe Interpretation of Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973), 112; T. Jennings, “On Ritual Knowledge”,Journal of Religion 62 (1982), 116: “Ritual Knowledge is gained not by detached observation or contemplation but through action ...”

    Google Scholar 

  19. M. Mauss,A General Theory of Magic (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 1902-03, Brain Trans. 1972, 1975 Reprint), 19. “Magic has been linked with a system of jural obligations, since in many places there are words and gestures which are binding sanctions.”

    Google Scholar 

  20. Malinowski,supra n. 19, at 93–94.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Mauss,supra n. 19, at 19. “It is true that legal actions may often acquire a ritual character and that contracts, oaths and trials by ordeal are to a certain extent sacramental. Nevertheless, the fact remains that although they contain ritual elements they are not magical rites in themselves. If they assume a special kind of efficacy or if they do more than merely establish contractual relations between person, they cease to be legal actions and do become magical or religious rites. Ritual acts, on the contrary, are essentially thought to be able to produce much more than a contract: rites are eminently effective; they are creative; theydo things.” (Emphasis in original). In light of the later work of J.L. Austin,see infra, at note 22, it is difficult to understand the distinction Mauss is trying to draw between rites which “do things” and “merely establishing contractual relations between persons” as if this were notdoing something too.

    Google Scholar 

  22. J.L. Austin, “Performative Utterances”,Philosophical Papers, eds. J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961, 1970 ed.), 233;How To Do Things With Words (New York: Oxford University Press, 1962, 1965 ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  23. S. J. Tambiah, “A Performative Approach to Ritual”, inCulture, Thought and Social Action: An Anthropological Perspective (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1985), 123–166.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See David Hume,A Treatise of Human Nature, bk. III, pt. ii, sec. 5 (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1739, 1896 ed.), 524, “Nay, even this we must not carry so far as to imagine that one, whom, by our quickness of understanding, we conjecture, from certain signs, to have an intention of deceiving us, is not bound by his expression or verbal promise, if we accept of it.”

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid. See “All these contradictions are easily accounted for, if the obligation of promises be merely a human invention for the convenience of society; but will never be explain'd, if it be something real and natural, arising from any action of the mind or body.”

    Google Scholar 

  26. For discussion of characteristics of propositional meaning, see G. Frege, “Thoughts”, inLogical Investigations, ed. P.T. Geach, trans. P.T. Geach and R.H. Stoothoff (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  27. See F. Stahl, “The Meaninglessness of Ritual”,Numen 26 (1979), 2.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Kertzer,supra n.11, at 69: “It is the very ambiguity of the symbols employed in ritual action that makes ritual useful in fostering solidarity without consensus”; J. Fernandez, “Symbolic Consensus in a Fang Reformative Cult”,American Anthropologist 67 (1965), 902.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Turner,The Ritual Process, supra n. 7, at 10–13. See also Arnold,supra n.2, at 44. “Legal institutions must constantly reconcile ideological conflicts, just as individuals reconcile them by shoving inconsistencies back into a sort of institutional subconscious mind.”

    Google Scholar 

  30. Barbara G. Myerhoff, “We don't wrap herring in a printed page: Fusion, fiction and continuity in secular ritual”,Secular Ritual, supra n. 13, at 199–200. “The fiction underlying ritual is twofold: first, that rituals are not made-up productions, and second, that the contradictions embraced by their symbols have been erased.”

    Google Scholar 

  31. D. Kennedy, “Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication”,Harvard Law Review 89 (1976), 1685, 1693.

    Google Scholar 

  32. P.S. Atiyah, “Form and Substance in Contract Law”, inidem, Essays on Contract (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), 93–94; P.S. Atiyah and R.S. Summers,Form and Substance in Anglo-American Law: A Comparative Study of Legal Reasoning, Legal Theory, and Legal Institutions (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  33. C. G. Hempel,Philosophy of Natural Science (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1966), ch. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  34. The nature of the “normative force” of law is largely irrelevant to the themes of this paper. Legal positivists hold that the “normative force” of law depends on the expectation of sanction or punishment upon its violation. H.L.A. Hart,The Concept of Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961), 6–7. Alternative theories maintain that laws express certain norms of behaviour which are obeyed not out of fear of the sanction attendant upon their transgression, but because of certain shared beliefs about a proper code of behaviour. Lon Fuller, “Positivism and Fidelity to Law”,Harvard Law Review 71 (1958), 630.

    Google Scholar 

  35. J. R. Searle,Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1969), 33–42.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., at 33.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., at 34.

  38. Ibid.,at 33–34.

  39. But see K. Olivecrona,Law as Fact (London: Stevens & Sons, 2nd ed., 1971), 221–222. Olivecrona rejects the view that performatives have effects independent of intentions.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Searle,supra n. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ibid., 50–53.

  42. Ibid., 51.

  43. Ibid.

  44. Forms for all of these actions are conveniently provided by manufacturers of legal forms. The sale of such corporate “form kits” as Blumberg's “Black Beauty” first manufactured in the 1870's and still used today, may have played an important role in the growth of the corporate form of business. See generally R. E. Seavoy,The Origins of the American Business Corporation, 1784–1855 (Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1982); A. D. Chandler, Jr.,The Visible Hand: The Managerial Revolution in American Business (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  45. See, e.g., E. A. Hoebel,The Law of Primitive Man (New York: Atheneum, 1974), 28; O.W. Holmes, “The Path of the Law”,Harvard Law Review 10 (1897), 457; S. Macaulay,Private Government (Madison: Disputes Processing Research Program of University of Wisconsin Law School, 1986), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  46. See, e.g., O. W. Holmes,The Common Law, ed. DeWolfe (Boston: Little, Brown & Company, 1881, 1963 ed.), 8; Pound,supra n. 4, at 77.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See generally R. von Ihering,Law as a Means to an End, trans. I. Husik (Boston: Boston Book Company, 1913); H.L.A. Hart,supra n.35, esp. chapters 1–3. The link of regulative rules to purposes and policies must include thecaveat that, “neither politicians nor scientists can fully, nor, often, even satisfactorily predict the consequences of legislation.” Moore,Law as Process, supra n.7, at 7. Moore makes a profound critique of the conventional self-image of law in the American legal profession as an intentionally constructed framework of social order.

    Google Scholar 

  48. See, e.g., Macaulay,Private Government,supra n.45.

  49. For discussion of the term category mistake, see G. Ryle,The Concept of Mind (New York: Barnes and Noble, 1949), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Lon Fuller, “Consideration and Form”,Columbia Law Review 45 (1945), 799, 801.

    Google Scholar 

  51. S.F.C. Milsom,Historical Foundations of the Common Law (Toronto: Butterworths, 1981, 2nd ed.), 250.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid.

  54. For instance, in Taiwan, the “chop” (or personal seal) is used instead of manual signatures to execute checks, promissory notes and other financial instruments and continues to play much the same role that the seal recently did in the West. Interestingly, business people typically keep their “chops” in safety deposit vaults, and the use of checks is not widespread among consumers. See Jane K. Winn, “Taiwan Ends Criminal Penalties for Bad Checks in Move to Reform its Financial System”,East Asian Executive Reports 8:8 (August 15, 1988), 9.

    Google Scholar 

  55. See e.g.,Danby v.Tucker, 31 W.R. 578 (1883).

  56. This was recognized by Lord Esher inCochrane v.Moore, (1890) 25 Q.B.D. 57: “I have come to the conclusion that in ordinary English language, and in legal effect, there cannot be a ‘gift’ without a giving and a taking. The giving and taking are the two contemporaneous reciprocal acts which constitute a ‘gift.’ They are a necessary part of the proposition that there has been a ‘gift.’ They are not evidence to prove that there has been a gift, but fact to be proved to constitute the proposition that there has been a gift.”

  57. P.S. Atiyah,The Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 144–145.

    Google Scholar 

  58. The Statute of Frauds, which requires that written documents accompany certain types of transactions, is often given as an example of “the evidentiary function” of legal rituals. This is a mistake. The Statute of Frauds is a regulative rule, not a constitutive one. It provides a defense to action on an oral promise (the legal ritual) which is deemed waived if not affirmatively pleaded by the defendant: Atiyah,ibid., at 205–208.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Robertson Smith,supra n.16, at lectures vi–xi.

    Google Scholar 

  60. D. Hooper and K. Whyld,The Oxford Companion to Chess (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), 267.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., at 145.

    Google Scholar 

  62. L. M. Friedman,History of American Law (New York: Touchstone, 2nd ed. 1985), 275–279; M. J. Horwitz,The Transformation of American Law, 1780–1860 (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1977), ch.6; Atiyah,supra n.61.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Confucian Analects, Bk. II, Ch. 3, transl. Legge (Taipei: Southern Materials Center, Inc., 1983 ed.). “If the People be led by laws, and uniformity sought to be given them by punishments, they will try to avoid the punishment, but have no sense of shame. If they be led by ritual, they will have the sense of shame, and moreover will become good.” See also H. Fingarette,Confucius — The Secular as Sacred (New York: Harper & Row, 1972), 28.

  64. J.G.A. Pocock, “Ritual, Language, Power: An essay on the apparent meanings of ancient Chinese philosophy”,Political Science 16 (1964), 6.

    Google Scholar 

  65. B. I. Schwartz,The World of Thought in Ancient China (Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press, 1985), 67–75. See also Douglas,supra n.6, at 62 (“As a social animal, man is a ritual animal. If ritual is suppressed in one form it crops up in others, more strongly the more intense the social interaction. Without the letters of condolence, telegrams of congratulations and even occasional postcards, the friendship of a separated friend is not a social reality. It has no existence without the rites of friendship. Social rituals create a reality which would be nothing without them.”)

    Google Scholar 

  66. Schwartz,supra n. 69, at 67.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Confucian Analects, Bk. II, Ch. 3,supra n. 67.

  68. Pocock,supra n.68, at 6.

    Google Scholar 

  69. See Arnold,supra n.2, at 10–17.

    Google Scholar 

  70. M. Bloch, “Introduction”, inPolitical Language and Oratory in Traditional Society, ed. Maurice Bloch (London: Academic Press, 1975), 22.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Geertz,supra n.18, at 112.

    Google Scholar 

  72. See works citedsupra n.30.

  73. Malinowski,supra n.20, at 13.

    Google Scholar 

  74. D. Hay, “Property, Authority and the Criminal Law”, inAlbion's Fatal Tree: Crime and Society in Eighteenth-Century England (New York: Pantheon Books, 1975), 32–33. One problem with Hay's analysis is that it confuses the constitutive rules of criminal procedure with the enactment of regulatory rules by Parliament.

    Google Scholar 

  75. See e.g. M. Bloch, “Symbols, Song, Dance and Features of Articulation: Is Religion an Extreme Form of Traditional Authority?”,European Journal of Sociology 15 (1974), 55–81; Bloch,supra n. 75, at 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  76. See B. Bettleheim,The Informed Heart (Glencoe: Free Press, 1960), 290–291 (Analysis of the Nazi ritual salute and its powerful political and psychological effectiveness in undermining dissent). Also see R. Bartlett,Trial by Fire and Water: The Mediaeval Judicial Ordeal (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986). (Analysis of the use of the ritual of the ordeal to consolidate the power of Charlemagne.)

    Google Scholar 

  77. Kertzer, (Many examples of use of ritual by opposition political groups); Eva Hunt, “Ceremonies of Confrontation and Submission: The Symbolic Dimension of Indian-Mexican Political Interaction”, inSecular Ritual, supra n. 13, at 124–47 (use of ritual by peasants to develop points of view opposed to ruling class).

    Google Scholar 

  78. T. Jennings, “On Ritual Knowledge”,Journal of Religion 62 (1982), 116.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Miranda v.Arizona, 384 U.S. 436 (1966).

  80. Ibid., at 444, 478–479.

  81. See G. M. Caplan, “Questioning Miranda”,Vanderbilt Law Review 38 (1985).

  82. W. Gangi, “Confessions: Historical Perspective and a Proposal”,Houston Law Review 10 (1973), 1087, 1103 “...[I]n an effort to eliminate swearing contests and protect the accused from police misconduct, Miranda constructed ‘prophylactic and deterrent rules that result in the release of the factually guilty even in cases in which blotting out the illegality would still leave an adjudicative factfinder convinced of the accused's guilt.’”

    Google Scholar 

  83. Janine Roberts, “Definition, Functions, and Typology of Rituals”, inRituals in Families and Family Therapy, ed. Imber-Black, Roberts and Whiting (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 1988), 26–33.

    Google Scholar 

  84. For a brief, though provocative, essay arguing for a reappraisal of the Warren Court, see M. J. Horwitz, “The Warren Court”,University of Chicago Law Review 55 (1988), 450, 456.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Additional information

Special Assistant Attorney General, Texas. The opinions expressed herein are those of the author and not necessarily those of the Texas Attorney General. Special thanks to Todd D. Rakoff, David Kertzer, David Park and Jane Kaufman Winn for their comments on earlier drafts of this article.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Winn, P.A. Legal ritual. Law Critique 2, 207–232 (1991). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01128678

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01128678

Keywords

Navigation