Skip to main content
Log in

Human and fundamental rights: What are they about?

  • Published:
Liverpool Law Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Conclusion

Human rights, distrusted by Bentham, through emergence ofGesellshaft, have sometimes been identified with rights of market men and gradually on an ad hoc basis and so have been given a ‘relational’ or relativist character for that reason. Such a view ignores the test of humanness or the ‘tele’ of human rights surviving any political association and the need for full development of human personality as an autonomous being inherent in full respect for all as moral persons. This disposes of the view of human rights in terms of rules of a game, or of connection between human rights and human action, or of the standard of the ‘prudent’ man or, finally, of the ideology of the rising bourgeoisie. Equally, that very test of humanness disposes of criticisms of the human rights theory based on a concern for implementation of rights, on ‘concentric circles’ based on the specific and concrete, on the ‘impossibility’ of liking the billions, on the distinction between ‘negative’, ‘positive’ and administrative rights, on the condition of being able to make ‘valid claims’ and thereby denying human rights to the deprived millions in poor countries, on the ‘social justice’ model, on the potential for ‘violence and conflict’ and, finally, on the ‘vagueness’ or subjectivity of human rights. An eclectic synthesis not between good and evil nor between right and wrong but between the extremes of the views presented in such critical explanations e.g. between the New Right and the New Left and between Hobbes and Rousseau) is what is needed in order to present a workable theory of human rights in the modern-day world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. E. Kamenka,Human Rights, ed. E. Kamenka and A.E.S. Tay, Edward Arnold, 1978, 6.

  2. 381 U.S. 479 (1965).

  3. C. Wellman, “A New Conception of Human Rights”,Human Rights, supra n.1 at 49.

  4. S.I. Benn, “Human Rights” — for whom and for what?,Human Rights, supra n.1 at 70–71.

  5. A. Gewirth,Human Rights, University of Chicago Press, 1982, 213.

  6. J. Kleinig, “Human Rights, legal rights and social change”,Human Rights, supra n.1 at 46.

  7. K.R. Minogue, “Natural Rights, ideology and the game of life”,Human Rights, supra n.1 at 21, 31.

  8. H.A. Bedau, “Why Do We Have The Right We Do?”, inHuman Rights, ed. E.F. Paul, E.D. Miller Jr. and L. Paul, Blackwell, 1984, 56, 61.

  9. A. Gewirth, “Human Rights”,supra n.5 at 137–38. See also A. Gewirth, “Can Utilitarianism Justify Any Moral Rights?”, inEthics, Economics and the Law, ed. J.R. Pennock and J.W. Chapman, New York University Press, 1982, chap.8.

  10. A. Gewirth, “The Epistemology of Human Rights”, inHuman Rights, ed. E.F. Paul et al,supra n.8 at 3. In a similar vein is the extrovertionist claim that such rights are “personally oriented, normatively moral requirements” (p.2).

  11. A.C. Danto, “Comment on Gewirth: Constructing an Epistemology”,Human Rights, supra n.8 at 30. In a similar vein, Golding says in the same volume that rights cannot be derived from the generic features of action alone. (M.P. Golding, “The Privacy of Welfare Rights”,Human Rights, supra n.8 at 131). He locates the ground of rights in “genuine personal good” (p.135).

  12. L. Lomasky, “Personal Projects as the foundation for Basic Rights”,Human Rights, 1984,supra n.8 at 38–39.

  13. Ibid. at 43,48 [“The value of being a project pursuer must be acknowledged, not the value of any and every particular object’ (p.53)].

  14. Thus Bedau considers that since no two persons experience the same socialisation and act in the same self-determinative ways, no two persons could have the same human nature. [H.A. Bedau,supra n.8 at 67]. This is, again, to take a very empirical and sociological/anthropological view of human nature, a view not warranted by the inherent truth about human nature when regard is had to the possibility and even likelihood of attainment of intersubjective rationality in man (considered later). Later, however, he comes to the view that through such socialisation and self-determination humans come to acquire “common human capacities” (ibid).

  15. A.E.S. Tay, “Marxism, socialism and human rights”,Human Rights, supra n.1 at 108.

  16. F. Bergman, “Two Critiques of the Traditional Theory of Human Rights”, XXIIINOMOS (1981), 56 (Human Rights, ed. J.R. Pennock and J.W. Chapman, New York University Press).

  17. Ibid. at 57–57.

  18. J. Narveson, “Human Rights: Which, if any, are there?”, inHuman Rights, 1981,supra n.16 at 179.

  19. K. Baier, “Merit and Race”, 8Philosophia (1978), 130–131.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Narveson,supra n.18 at 194.

  21. See also H. Shue,Rights in the Light of Duties, Human Rights and U.S. Foreign Policy, ed. P.G. Brown and D. MacLean, I.P.P. Press, 1979, 65, where it is argued that there is no clear, morally relevant distinction between negative and positive rights.

  22. S.M. Okin, “Liberty and Welfare: Some Issues in Human Rights Theory”,Human Rights, 1981,supra n.16 at 241–42.

  23. R.H. Tawney,The Acquisitive Society, Collins, 1965, 54.

  24. J. Locke,The First Treatise of Government, sec.42.

  25. J. Feinberg,Rights, Justice and Bounds of Liberty, Princeton University Press, 1980, 153; A. Gerwirth, “The Epistemology of Human Rights”,Human Rights, 1984,supra n.8 at 7; A.S. Rosenbaum, ed.,The Philosophy of Human Rights: International Perspectives, Greenwood Press, 1980, chap.8 (A. Levine). Cf. J. Donnelly, “Human Rights as Natural Rights”, 4Human Rights Quarterly (1982), 391, 395. A.R. White has shown that certain kinds of rights in one person give rise to no duties in others and, hence, to no claims by the former that such duties be exercised by the latter. [A. Stewart, ed.,Law, Morality and Rights, Reidel, 1983, 156–57.] Analyses of rights in terms of claims usually go hand in hand with an emphasis on right to property and rights against people, both of which are rights to something done to one, rather than right to do anything.(p.154). This is the sense used in the context of a right to a minimum standard of life, which includes ‘claim-rights’ exercised by others as ‘trustees’ on behalf of others unable to exercise their rights, as explained later. In other cases rights do not imply claims. Finally, sometimes two senses of rights are introduced by some philosophers, viz, the right to act and the right to receive; the latter of which is then analysed as a claim on others, e.g., as a claim to their non-interference.

  26. C. Beitz, “Human Rights and Social Justice”,Human Rights and U.S. Foreign Policy, supra n.21 at 48.

  27. Ibid., at 59.

  28. A.M. Honoré, “Social Justice”,Essays in Legal Philosophy, ed. R.S. Summers, Blackwell, 1970, 61, 92, 93.

  29. A.S. Rosenbaum, ed., “The Philosophy of Human Rights”,supra n.25, chap.9 (E.Shmuli).

  30. A. Buchanan, “What is so Special About Rights?”, inEquality and Liberty, ed. E.F. Paul, F.D. Miller Jr. and J. Paul, Blackwell, 1985, 61–83.

  31. J. Lenoble, “The Implicit Ideology of Human Rights and its Legal Expression”, VIII(2)Liverpool Law Review (1986), 153, 159.

  32. Ibid., at 160.

  33. [1964] A.C. 40, 64–65.

  34. Inland Revenue Commissioners v.Rassminster Ltd. [1980] A.C. 952, 1011;Khawaja v. Secretary of State for the Home Department, [1984] A.C. 74, 110.

  35. [1942] A.C. 206, 227–28.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Narain, J. Human and fundamental rights: What are they about?. Liverpool Law Rev 15, 163–187 (1993). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01079918

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01079918

Keywords

Navigation