Skip to main content
Log in

Classical and connectionist models: Levels of description

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

To begin, I introduce an analysis of interlevel relations that allows us to offer an initial characterization of the debate about the way classical and connectionist models relate. Subsequently, I examine a compatibility thesis and a conditional claim on this issue.

With respect to the compatibility thesis, I argue that, even if classical and connectionist models are not necessarily incompatible, the emergence of the latter seems to undermine the best arguments for the Language of Thought Hypothesis, which is essential to the former.

I attack the conditional claim of connectionism to eliminativism, presented by Ramsey et al. (1990), by discrediting their discrete characterization of common-sense psychological explanations and pointing to the presence of a moderate holistic constraint.

Finally, I conclude that neither of the arguments considered excludes the possibility of viewing connectionist models as forming a part of a representational theory of cognition that dispenses with the Language of Thought Hypothesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Burge, T.: 1979, ‘Individualism and the Mental’, in P. A. French et al. (eds.),Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4, 73–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chater, N. and M. Oaksford: 1990, ‘Autonomy, Implementation and Cognitive Architecture: A Reply to Fodor and Pylyshyn’,Cognition 34, 93–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A.: 1989a,Microcognition, Philosophy, Cognitive Science. and Parallel Distributed Processing, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A.: 1989b, ‘Connectionism, Non-conceptual Content and Representational Redescription’, University of Sussex, Brighton, Serial no. CSRP 143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D.: 1971, ‘Intentional Systems’,Journal of Philosophy 8, 87–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, J. and D. Ballard: 1982, ‘Connectionist Models and their Properties’,Cognitive Science 6, 205–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H.: 1978, ‘Mental Representation’,Erkenntnis 13, 9–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.: 1975,The Language of Thought, Harvester Press, Hassocks, Sussex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.: 1987,Psychosemantics, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.: 1980, ‘Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology’,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, 63–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.: 1991, ‘A Modal Argument For Narrow Content’,The Journal of Philosophy 83, 5–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. and B. McLaughlin: 1990, ‘Connectionism and the Problem of Systematicity; Why Smolensky's Solution Doesn't Work’,Cognition 35, 183–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. and Z. W. Pylyshyn: 1988, ‘Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis’,Cognition 28, 3–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I.: 1993, ‘The Psychology of Folk Psychology’,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16, 15–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hanson, S. and D. J. Burr: 1990, ‘What Connectionist Models Learn: Learning and Representation in Connectionist Networks’,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13, 471–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, D. O.: 1949,The Organization of Behavior, John Wiley, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. and J. Tienson: 1989, ‘Representations without Rules’,Philosophical Topics 17, 147–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, J. L., D. E. Rumelhart, and G. E. Hinton: 1986, ‘The Appeal of Parallel Distributed Processing’, in Rumelhart and McClelland (1986a), pp. 3–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, P. and J. McDowell (eds.): 1986,Subject, Thought and Context, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: 1975, ‘The Meaning and ‘Meaning’’, in H. Putnam,Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2: Mind, Language and Reality Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 215–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H.: 1988,Representation and Reality, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W., S. Stich, and J. Garon: 1990, ‘Connectionism, Eliminativism, and the Future of Folk Psychology’, in J. Tomberlin (ed.),Philosophical Perspectives, Vol.4, Ridgeview, Atascadero, California, pp. 499–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D. E., G. E. Hinton, and J. L. McClelland: 1986, ‘A General Framework for Parallel Distributed Processing’, in Rumelhart and McClelland (1986a), pp. 45–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D. E. and J. L. McClelland (eds.): 1986a,Parallel Distributed Processing Explorations in the Microstructure of Cognition, 2 vols., MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D. E. and J. L. McClelland: 1986b, ‘PDP Models and General Issues in Cognitive Science’, in Rumelhart and McClelland (1986a), pp. 110–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smolensky, P.: 1988, ‘On the Proper Treatment of Connectionism’,Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11, 1–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodfield, A. (ed.): 1982,Thought and Object. Essays on Intentionality, Clarendon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Corbí, J.E. Classical and connectionist models: Levels of description. Synthese 95, 141–168 (1993). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01064585

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01064585

Keywords

Navigation