Skip to main content
Log in

Rights, neutrality, and the oppressive power of the state

  • Published:
Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

References

  1. Benjamin Constant,Principles of Politics Applicable to All Representative Governments, inBenjamin Constant: Political Writings, trans. and ed. Biancamaria Fontana (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), p. 176.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Judith Shklar,Ordinary Vices (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1984), p. 237.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ronald Dworkin, “Liberalism,” in hisA Matter of Principle (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Alasdair MacIntyre,After Virtue, second edition (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1984), p. 195.

    Google Scholar 

  5. This argument appears in chapter two of a manuscript still in progress entitledBeyond Neutrality: Perfectionism and Politics.

  6. Will Kymlicka, “Liberal Individualism and Liberal Neutrality,”Ethics 99 (1989): 884.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Bruce Ackerman,Social Justice and the Liberal State (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980), p. 369.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., p. 363.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Thus, Jeremy Waldron quotes T. S. Eliot as opposing “the ideal of a neutral society” in a book that Eliot published just before the Second World War; but Waldron adds that “I have managed to find no evidence that any liberal view that Eliot was opposing was ever actually formulated in these terms” (Jeremy Waldron, “Legislation and Moral Neutrality,” in Robert E. Goodin and Andrew Reeve, eds.,Liberal Neutrality (London: Routledge, 1989), p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Shklar,Ordinary Vices, pp. 237–38.

  11. In “Liberalism,” cited above.

  12. Ibid., p. 197.

  13. Ibid., p. 198.

  14. Dworkin, “Liberalism,” p. 183; see also Will Kymlicka,Liberalism, Community, and Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  15. These phrases from the mission statement of the N.E.A. are from a passage cited by David Schwartz in “Can Intrinsic Value Theorists Justify Subsidies for Contemporary Art?”Public Affairs Quarterly, forthcoming.

  16. Dworkin, “Liberalism,” p. 197.

  17. For arguments to this effect, see Stephen Macedo,Liberal Virtues (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990), ch. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Dworkin, “Liberalism,” p. 197.

  19. That this is Dworkin's motivation emerges clearly in “Liberalism,” p. 197.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Sher, G. Rights, neutrality, and the oppressive power of the state. Law Philos 14, 185–201 (1995). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01001043

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF01001043

Keywords

Navigation