Skip to main content
Log in

Akrasia, reasons, and causes

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Conclusion

We may, and should, reject Davidson's (P2) — the claim that any agent who judges (unconditionally) that it is better to do x than to do y is more strongly motivated to do x than to do y — without having to abandon a causal theory of action. (P2) is false. The connection between unconditional judgments and the balance of an agent's motivation is more complex than Davidson thinks; and this holds as well for the connection between intentions and motivations. The extent to which an agent is self-controlled is also an important factor. This is not to say, however, that there is no connection, nor that to explain an intentional action by citing the reason(s) for which it was intended and performed is not to give a causal explanation of the action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Bibliography

  1. Aristotle: Nicomachcan Ethics, in W. D. Ross (ed.), Works of Aristotle, Vol. IX (Oxford University Press, London, 1915).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Audi, R.: 1979, ‘Weakness of will and practical judgment’, Noûs 13, pp. 173–196.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Brand, M.: 1979, ‘The fundamental question in action theory’, Noûs 13, pp. 131–151.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Brandt, R.: 1979, A Theory of the Good and the Right (Clarendon Press, Oxford).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Davidson, D.: 1980, Essays on Actions and Events (Clarendon Press, Oxford).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Davidson, D.: 1978, ‘Intending’, in Y. Yovel (ed.) Philosophy of History and Action (D. Reidel, Dordrecht), pp. 41–60. Reprinted in [5].

    Google Scholar 

  7. Davidson, D.: 1976, ‘Hempel on explaining action’, in [5], pp. 261–276. Reprinted from Erkenntnis 10, pp. 239–253.

  8. Davidson, D.: 1974, ‘Psychology as philosophy’, in S. C. Brown (ed.), Philosophy of Psychology (Barnes and Noble, New York), pp. 41–52. Reprinted in [5].

    Google Scholar 

  9. Davidson, D.: 1973, ‘Freedom to act’, in T. Honderich (ed.), Essays on Freedom of Action (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London), pp. 137–156. Reprinted in [5].

    Google Scholar 

  10. Davidson, D.: 1970, ‘Mental events’, in L. Foster and J. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory (University of Massachusetts Press), pp. 79–101. Reprinted in [5].

  11. Davidson, D.: 1969, ‘How is weakness of the will possible?’, in J. Feinberg (ed.), Moral Concepts (Clarendon Press, Oxford), pp. 93–113. Reprinted in [5].

    Google Scholar 

  12. Goldman, A.: 1970, A Theory of Human Action (Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hare, R.: 1963, Freedom and Reason (Oxford University Press, Oxford).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Pears, D.: 1982, ‘How easy is akrasia?’, Philosophia 11, pp. 33–50.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Plato: Protagoras, tr. C. C. Taylor (Clarendon Press Oxford, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Rorty, A.: 1980, ‘Where does the akratic break take place?’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58, pp. 333–346.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Stoutland, F.: 1980, ‘Oblique causation and reasons for action’, Synthese 43, pp. 351–367.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Taylor, C. C.: 1980, ‘Plato, Hare, and Davidson on akrasia’, Mind 89, pp. 499–518.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Watson, G.: 1977, ‘Skepticism about weakness of will’, Philosophical Review 86, pp. 316–339.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mele, A.R. Akrasia, reasons, and causes. Philosophical Studies 44, 345–368 (1983). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00353541

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00353541

Keywords

Navigation