Advertisement

Journal of Philosophical Logic

, Volume 8, Issue 1, pp 171–196 | Cite as

Interval semantics for tense logic: Some remarks

  • I. L. Humberstone
Article

Keywords

Tense Logic Interval Semantic 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  1. [1]
    L.Åqvist, ‘“Next” and “Ought”: Alternative Foundations for von Wright's Tense Logic with an Application to Deontic Logic’, Logique et Analyse 9 (1966), 231–51.Google Scholar
  2. [2]
    J.Clifford, ‘Tense Logic and the Logic of Change’, Logique et Analyse 9 (1966), 210–30.Google Scholar
  3. [3]
    M. J. Cresswell, ‘Frames and Models in Modal Logic’, in J. N. Crossley (ed.), Algebra and Logic, Springer-Verlag (Lecture Notes in Mathematics Series, No. 450), 1975, pp. 63–86.Google Scholar
  4. [4]
    D. R.Dowty, ‘Toward a Semantic Analysis of Verb Aspect and the English “Imperfective” Progressive’, Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (1977), 45–77.Google Scholar
  5. [5]
    K.Fine, ‘Vagueness, Truth and Logic’, Synthese 30 (1975), 265–300.Google Scholar
  6. [6]
    A.Grünbaum, ‘Whitehead's Method of Extensive Abstraction’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 4 (1953/4), 215–226.Google Scholar
  7. [7]
    C. L.Hamblin, ‘Instants and Intervals’, Stadium Generale 27 (1971), 127–134.Google Scholar
  8. [8]
    C. L. Hamblin, ‘Starting and Stopping’, in E. Freeman and W. Sellars (eds.), Basic Issues in the Philosophy of Time, Open Court, 1971, pp. 86–101.Google Scholar
  9. [9]
    J. A. W. Kamp, ‘Two Theories about Adjectives’, in E. L. Keenan (ed.), Formal Semantics of Natural Language, Cambridge, 1975, pp. 123–155.Google Scholar
  10. [10]
    S. A. Kripke, ‘Semantical Analysis of Intuitionistic Logic, I’, in J. N. Crossley and M. A. Dummett (eds.), Formal Systems and Recursive Funtions, Amsterdam, 1965, pp. 92–130.Google Scholar
  11. [11]
    H. S.Leonard and N.Goodman, ‘The Calculus of Individuals and its Uses’, Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (1940), 45–55.Google Scholar
  12. [12]
    B.Medlin, ‘The Origin of Motion’, Mind 72 (1963), 155–75.Google Scholar
  13. [13]
    N.Rescher and A.Urquhart, Temporal Logic, Springer-Verlag, New York, 1971.Google Scholar
  14. [14]
    K.Segerberg, ‘On the Logic of “To-morrow”’, Theoria 33 (1967), 45–52.Google Scholar
  15. [15]
    K.Segerberg, ‘Propositional Logics Related to Heytings's and Johansson's’, Theoria 34 (1968), 26–61.Google Scholar
  16. [16]
    K.Segerberg, ‘Modal Logics with Linear Alternative Relations’, Theoria 36 (1970), 301–322.Google Scholar
  17. [17]
    R.Sorabji, ‘Aristotle on the Instant of Change’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supp. Volume) 50 (1976), 69–89.Google Scholar
  18. [18]
    B. M.Taylor, ‘Tense and Continuity’, Linguistics and Philosophy 1 (1977), 199–220.Google Scholar
  19. [19]
    R. H.Thomason and R. C.Stalnaker, ‘A Semantic Theory of Adverbs’, Linguistic Inquiry 4 (1973), 195–220.Google Scholar
  20. [20]
    D. Wiggins, ‘The De Re “Must”: a Note on the Logical Form of Essentialist Claims’, in G. Evans and J. H. McDowell (eds.), Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics, Oxford, 1976, pp. 285–312.Google Scholar
  21. [21]
    G. H.vonWright, ‘And Next’, Acta Philosophica Fennica 18 (1965), 293–304.Google Scholar
  22. [22]
    G. H. von Wright, ‘And Then’, Commentationes Physico-Mathematicae (Soc. Sci. Fenn.) 32 (1966).Google Scholar
  23. [23]
    G. H.vonWright, ‘Always’, Theoria 34 (1968), 208–221.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Co 1979

Authors and Affiliations

  • I. L. Humberstone
    • 1
  1. 1.Monash UniversityMelbourneAustralia

Personalised recommendations