Skip to main content
Log in

Research note Partial single-peakedness: An extension and clarification

  • Why So Much Stability?
  • Published:
Public Choice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Niemi (1969), in an important but neglected paper, found that when orderings were drawn from a simulation based on the impartial culture, the greater the proportion of voter orderings that were single-peaked (a condition he called partial single-peakedness), the more likely was there to be a transitive group ordering. Niemi also found that the likelihood of transitivity increased with n, group size — approaching one as n grew large. Niemi's simulation was restricted to the case of three alternatives. Also, he provided no theoretical explanation for the results of his simulation. Here we provide a theoretical explanation for Niemi's results in terms of a model based on the idea of net preferences, and we extend his results for the general case of any finite number of alternatives, m, for electorates that are large relative to the number of alternatives being considered. In addition to providing a rationale for Niemi's (1969) simulation results, the ideas of net preferences and opposite preference we make use of have a wide range of potential applications.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

References

  • Arrow, K.J. (1963). Social choice and individual values, 2nd Edition. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bell, C.E. (1978). What happens when majority rule breaks down: Some probability calculations. Public Choice 33(2): 121–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (1958). The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Condorcet, Marquis de (1985). Essai sur l'application de l'analyse à la probabilité des decisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. Paris.

  • Gaertner, W., and Heinecke, A. (1978). Cyclically mixed preferences: A necessary and sufficient condition for transitivity of the social preference relation. In H.W. Gottinger and W. Leinfellner, Decision theory and social ethnics: Issues in social choice, 169–186. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gehrlein, W.V., and Fishburn, P.C. (1976). The probability of the paradox of voting: A computable solution. Journal of Economic Theory 13(1) (August): 14–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, G.H. (1973). On a class of equilibrium conditions for majority rule. Econometrica 41: 285–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuga, K., and Nagatani, H. (1974). Voter antagonism and the paradox of voting. Econometrica 42(6) (November): 1045–1067.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R.D. (1976). Intransitivities in multidimensional voting models and some implications for agenda control. Journal of Economic Theory 12: 472–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey, R., and Wendell, R. (1976). Voting equilibria in multidimensional choice spaces. Mathematics of Operations Research 1: 144–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, N. (1970). A necessary and sufficient condition for transitive majority orderings. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Nicholson, M.B. (1965). Conditions for the ‘voting paradox’ for committee decisions. Metroeconomica 7: 29–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niemi, R.G. (1969). Majority decision-making with partial unidimensionality. American Political Science Review 63: 488–497.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niemi, R.G. (1970). The occurrence of the paradox of voting in university elections. Public Choice 8: 91–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niemi, R.G. (1983). Why so much stability?! Another opinion. Public Choice 41: 261–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niemi, R.G., and Weisberg, H.F. (1968). A mathematical solution for the probability of the paradox of voting. Behavioral Science 13: 317–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plott, C. (1967). A notion of equilibrium and its possibility under major rule. American Economic Review 57: 787–806.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W.H. (1961). Voting and the summation of preferences: An interpretive bibliographic essay of selected developments during the last decade. American Political Science Review 55: 900–911.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. (1980). Implications from the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions. American Political Science Review 74(1): 432–446, and Reply, 456–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. (1982). Liberalism against populism: A confrontation between the theory of democracy and the theory of social choice. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schofield, N. (1978). Instability of simple dynamic games. Review of Economic Studies 45(3): 575–594.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.K. (1966). A Possibility theorem on majority decisions. Econometrica 34: 491–499.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A.K. Social choice theory. In K.J. Arrow and M. Intriligator (Eds.), Handbook of mathematical economics, forthcoming.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Additional information

We are indebted to Jonathan Riley for helpful bibliographic assistance, and to Sue Pursche and the staff of the Word Processing Center, School of Social Sciences, U.C.I. for typing several earlier drafts of this manuscript.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Feld, S.L., Grofman, B. Research note Partial single-peakedness: An extension and clarification. Public Choice 51, 71–80 (1986). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00141686

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00141686

Keywords

Navigation