Skip to main content
Log in

An epistemic analysis of explanations and causal beliefs

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Conclusion

The analyses of explanation and causal beliefs are heavily dependent on using probability functions as models of epistemic states. There are, however, several aspects of beliefs that are not captured by such a representation and which affect the outcome of the analyses.

One dimension that has been neglected in this article is the temporal aspect of the beliefs. The description of a single event naturally involves the time it occurred. Some analyses of causation postulate that the cause must not occur later than the effect. If we want this kind of causality it is easy to add the appropriate clause to (CAUS). An alternative is not to rule out backwards causation or causal loops a priori, but expect that (CAUS), via the properties of the contraction P -C , will result in the desired temporal relation between C and E. One way of ensuring this is to postulate that when the probability function P is contracted to P -C , the probabilities of all events that occurred before C remain the same in P -C as in P. This means that all beliefs about the history of events up to C are left unaltered in the construction of the hypothetical state of belief P -C .

In conclusion, I hope to have shown that, in spite of these limitations, (EXP) and (CAUS) provide viable analyses of explanation and causality between single events for the case when epistemic states can be described by probability functions. I have also shown that the two analyses can be used to explicate the close connections between the two notions. These analyses reduce the problems of explanation and causality, hopefully in a non-circular way, to the problem of identifying contractions of states of belief.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Bibliography

  • Alchourrón, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., and Makinson, D. (1985): “On the logic of theory change: Partial meet contraction and revision functions”, Journal of Symbolic Logic 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1975): Posterior Analytics, translated with notes by J. Barnes (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T. L. and Rosenberg, A. (1981): Hume and the Problem of Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dray, W. (1957): Laws and Explanation in History (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1976): “Relevance and redundancy in deductive explanations”, Philosophy of Science 43, 420–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1979): “Conditionals and changes of belief”, in The Logic and Epistemology of Scientific Change, I. Niiniluoto and R. Tuomela, eds. (Amsterdam: North-Holland), 381–404.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1980): “A pragmatic approach to explanation”, Philosophy of Science 47, 404–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1981): “An epistemic approach to conditionals”, American Philosophical Quarterly 18, 203–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1982): “Rules for rational changes of belief”, in Philosophical Essays Dedicated to Lennart Åqvist on his Fiftieth Birthday, T. Pauli, ed. (Department of Philosophy, Uppsala).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1986): “The dynamics of belief: Contractions and revisions of probability functions”, Topoi 5, 24–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1988a): Knowledge in Flux: Modeling the Dynamics of Epistemic States (Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books, MIT Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1988b): “Causation and the dynamics of belief”, in Causation in Decision, Belief Change and Statistics II, W. L. Harper and B. Skyrms, eds. (Dordrecht: Kluwer), 85–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Good, I. J. (1961–2): “A causal calculus I–II”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 11, 305–318, and 12, 43–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granger, C. W. J. (1969): “Investigating causal relations by econometric models and crosspectral methods”, Econometrica 37, 424–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Granger, C. W. J. (1988): “Causality testing in a decision science”, in Causation, Chance and Credence, B. Skyrms and W. L. Harper, eds. (Dordrecht: Reidel), 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, B. (1975): “Explanations - Of what?” (manuscript, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University).

  • Harper, W. L. (1978): “Bayesian learning models with revision of evidence”, Philosophia 7, 357–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1962): “Deductive-nomological vs. statistical explanation”, in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 3, H. Feigl and G. Maxwell, eds. (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press), 98–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965): Aspects of Scientific Explanation (New York: Free Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1968): “Maximal specificity and lawlikeness in probabilistic explanation”. Philosophy of Science 35, 116–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesslow, G. (1976): “Two notes on the probabilistic approach to causality”, Philosophy of Science 43, 290–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748): An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (London).

  • Keynes, J. M. (1921): Treatise on Probability (London: Macmillan).

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1977): “Direct inference”, The Journal of Philosophy 74, 5–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1988): “Four themes in statistical explanation”, in Causation in Decision, Belief Change, and Statistics II, W. L. Harper and B. Skyrms, eds. (Dordrecht: Reidel), 195–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973): “Causation”, Journal of Philosophy 70, 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1976): “Probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities”, Philosophical Review 85, 297–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1974): The Cement of the Universe (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pizzi, C. (1988): “Causal preemption and iterated conditionals”, in Temi e prospettive della logica e della filosofia delta scienza contemporanee 2, (Bologna: CLUEB) 129–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1968): The Logic of Scientific Discovery, revised edition (London: Hutchinson).

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1956): The Direction of Time (Berkeley).

  • Rott, H. D. (1982): “Gärdenfors' epistemologische Explikation wissenschaftlichen Erklärung” (manuscript, Seminar für Logik und Wissenschaftstheorie, Universität München).

  • Salmon, W. C. (1971): Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh).

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1980): “Probabilistic causality”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61, 50–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (1983): Wissenschaftliche Erklärung (Dissertation, Karl-Franzens-Universität, Graz).

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. J. (1959): “Explanation and prediction in evolutionary theory”, Science 130 (no. 3374), 477–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sintonen, M. (1984): The Pragmatics of Explanation (Amsterdam: North-Holland).

    Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1983a): “Deterministic and probabilistic reasons and causes”, Erkenntnis 19, 371–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spohn, W. (1983b): “Probabilistic causality: from Hume via Suppes to Granger”, in Causalità e modelli probabilistici, M. C. Galavotti and G. Gambetta, eds. (Bologna: CLUEB).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller, W. (1983): Erklärung, Begründung, Kausalität, second edition (Berlin: Springer-Verlag).

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1970): A Probabilistic Theory of Causality (Amsterdam: North-Holland).

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller, P. (1976): “Conditionalization, observation and change of preference”, in Foundations of Probability Theory, Statistical Inference, and Statistical Theories of Science 1, W. L. Harper and C. H. Hooker, eds. (Dordrecht: Reidel).

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1977): “The pragmatics of explanation”, American Philosophical Quarterly 14, 143–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980): The Scientific Image (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Vercelli, A. (1986): “Probabilistic causality and economic models: Suppes, Keynes, Granger”, Quaderni dell'Istituto di Economica (Siena: Universitá degli Studi di Siena).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gärdenfors, P. An epistemic analysis of explanations and causal beliefs. Topoi 9, 109–124 (1990). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00135892

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00135892

Keywords

Navigation