Advertisement

Zeitschrift für Ethik und Moralphilosophie

, Volume 1, Issue 2, pp 263–277 | Cite as

Realism, Constructivism, and Intuitionism. Outline of an Unorthodox Hybrid Theory

  • Bert HeinrichsEmail author
Essay
  • 26 Downloads

Abstract

In this paper, I will suggest an unorthodox hybrid theory of ethical justification that combines, on an ontological level, a realist approach with constructivist elements. On an epistemological level, the realist part of the theory will be squared with an intuitionist account. Eventually, the suggested hybrid theory will take the form of an intuitionist ethics of persons. I will start with briefly sketching the ontological shape of the relevant concept of person whereby I will extensively draw on Kant and endorse a realist reading of his ethical theory (2.). Subsequently, I will explain why and how constructivist elements must complement the picture (3.). Then, I will focus on the epistemological shape of the theory. In particular, I will suggest an intuitionist reading of Kant’s doctrine of “the fact of reason” (4.). Next, I will briefly comment on classical intuitionism and on Bernard William’s notion of convergence in ethics (5.). Subsequently, I will compare my approach with Robert Audi’s attempt to refine a Rossian type of intuitionism (6.). Finally, I will revisit the charge of dogmatism that has traditionally been raised against intuitionism (7.).

Keywords

Metaethics Realism Constructivism Intuitionism ethics of persons 

References

  1. Ameriks, Karl. 1981. Kant’s Deduction of Freedom and Morality. Journal of the History of Philosophy 19: 53-79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Audi, Robert. 2004. The Good in the Right. A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Baldwin, Thomas. 2002. The Three Phases of Intuitionism. In Ethical Intuitionism. Re-evaluations. Ed. Philip Stratton-Lake, 92-112. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Beck, Lewis White. 1961. Das Faktum der Vernunft: Zur Rechtfertigungsproblematik in der Ethik. Kant-Studien 52: 271-282.Google Scholar
  5. Heinrichs, Bert. 2013. Moralische Intuition und ethische Rechtfertigung. Eine Untersuchung zum ethischen Intuitionismus. Münster: Mentis.Google Scholar
  6. Joas, Hans. 2011. Die Sakralität der Person. Eine neue Genealogie der Menschenrechte. Berlin: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  7. Kant, Immanuel. 1804. Preisschrift über die Fortschritte der Metaphysik. In Akademie-Ausgabe, Bd. XX, 253-332 [=Preisschrift].Google Scholar
  8. Kant, Immanuel. 1996. The Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [= MM].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Kant, Immanuel. 1997. Critique of Practical Reason. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [= CpR].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Kant, Immanuel. 1998. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated and edited by Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press [= GMM].CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996a. The Sources of Normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Korsgaard, Christine M. 1996b. Creating the Kingdom of Ends. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Korsgaard, Christine M. 2004. Fellow Creatures: Kantian Ethics and Our Duties to Animals. The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Delivered at University of Michigan February 6, 2004. https://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/k/korsgaard_2005.pdf (25.11.2018).Google Scholar
  14. Korsgaard, Christine M. 2008. Realism and Constructivism in Twentieth-Century Moral Philosoohy. In The Constitution of Agency. Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology. 302-326. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Luków, Pawel. 1993. The Fact of Reason. Kant’s Passage to Ordinary Moral Knowledge. Kant-Studien 84: 204-221.Google Scholar
  16. Mackie, John Leslie. 1990. Ethics. Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  17. McDowell, John. 1996. Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  18. McDowell, John. 1998. Two Sorts of Naturalism. In Mind, Value, and Reality. 167-197. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Moore, George Edward. 1993. Principia Ethica. Revised Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Nowell-Smith, Patrick H. 1954. Ethics. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
  21. Pallikkathayil, Japa. 2010. Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity. Ethics 121: 116-147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Platts, Mark. 1979. Ways of Meaning: An Introduction to a Philosophy of Language. London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Prichard, Harold Arthur. 2002. Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake? In Moral Writings. 7‑20. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Rawls, John. 1980. Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory. Journal of Philosophy 77: 515-572.Google Scholar
  25. Richardson, Henry S. 1990. Specifying Norms as a Way to resolve Concrete Ethical Problems. Philosophy & Public Affairs 19: 279-310.Google Scholar
  26. Ross, William David. 2002. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Schmucker, Josef. 1997. Der Formalismus und die materialen Zweckprinzipien in der Ethik Kants. In Kant. Analysen – Probleme – Kritik, Bd. III. Ed. Hariolf Oberer, 99-156. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.Google Scholar
  28. Sidgwick, Henry. 1981. The Methods of Ethics. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  29. Strawson, Peter F. 1949. Ethical Intuitionism. Philosophy 24: 23-33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sturma, Dieter. 1997. Philosophie der Person. Die Selbstverhältnisse von Subjektivität und Moralität. Paderborn: Schöningh.Google Scholar
  31. Sturma, Dieter. 2008. Die Natur der Freiheit: Integrativer Naturalismus in der theoretischen und praktischen Philosophie. Philosophisches Jahrbuch 115: 385-396.Google Scholar
  32. Sturma, Dieter; Heinrichs, Bert. 2015. Bioethik – Hauptströmungen, Methoden und Disziplinen. In Handbuch Bioethik. Ed. Dieter Sturma und Bert Heinrichs, 1‑8. Stuttgart: Metzler.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Williams, Bernard. 1993. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Fontana Press.Google Scholar
  34. Williams, Bernard. 1996. History, morality, and the test of reflection. In The Sources of Normativity. Ed. Christine M. Korsgaard, 210-218. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Wood, Allen W. 1999. Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag GmbH Deutschland, ein Teil von Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institut für Wissenschaft und Ethik (IWE)Rheinische Friedrich-Wilhelms-Universität BonnBonnGermany
  2. 2.Institute of Neuroscience and Medicine: Ethics in the Neurosciences (INM-8)Forschungszentrum JülichJülichGermany

Personalised recommendations