Skip to main content
Log in

The Gettier Intuition from South America to Asia

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article examines whether people share the Gettier intuition (viz. that someone who has a true justified belief that p may nonetheless fail to know that p) in 24 sites, located in 23 countries (counting Hong Kong as a distinct country) and across 17 languages. We also consider the possible influence of gender and personality on this intuition with a very large sample size. Finally, we examine whether the Gettier intuition varies across people as a function of their disposition to engage in “reflective” thinking.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Alai 2015 for further discussion.

  2. Starmans and Friedman 2012; Turri et al. 2015; Machery et al. forthcoming b.

  3. In Colombia, the 100-point confidence scales for Knowledge 1 and Knowledge 2 were replaced with 7-point scales.

  4. In Korea the 18-item NFC scale was replaced with the standardized 15-item NFC scale in Korean (Kim 2007).

  5. While our scale ranged from 1 to 7, the data from Germany ranged from 1 to 8. We do not know where the disagreement comes from. Assuming a coding error, we decided to transform the 8’s into 7’s.

  6. TIPI codes for emotional stability, the inverse of neuroticism. So high scores correspond to a low neuroticism.

References

  • Adleberg, T., Thompson, M., & Nahmias, E. (2015). Do men and women have different philosophical intuitions? Further data. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 615–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alai, M. (2015). Regimenting the ordinary notions of knowledge and justification after Gettier. In M. L. Bianca & P. Piccari (Eds.), Epistemology of ordinary knowledge (pp. 247–261). Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antognazza, M. R. (2015). The benefit to philosophy of the study of its history. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 23, 161–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Antony, L. (2012). Different voices or perfect storm: Why are there so few women in philosophy? Journal of Social Philosophy, 43, 227–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson, J. (2013). Experimental attacks on intuitions and answers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86, 495–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., & Stich, S. (2014). Gender and philosophical intuition. In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy (Vol. 2, pp. 307–346). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cacioppo, J. T., Petty, R. E., & Kao, C. F. (1984). The efficient assessment of need for cognition. Journal of Personality Assessment, 48, 306–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colaço, D., Buckwalter, W., Stich, S. P., & Machery, E. (2014). Epistemic intuitions in fake-barn thought experiments. Episteme, 2, 199–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutant, J. (2015). The legend of the justified true belief analysis. Philosophical Perspectives, 29, 95–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. T. (2009). Do judgments about freedom and responsibility depend on who you are? Personality differences in intuitions about compatibilism and incompatibilism. Consciousness and Cognition, 18, 342–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. T. (2012). The philosophical personality argument. Philosophical Studies, 161, 227–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A., & Cokely, E. (2013). Predicting philosophical disagreement. Philosophy Compass, 8, 978–989.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S. (2005). Cognitive reflection and decision making. The Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19, 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friesdorf, R., Conway, P., & Gawronski, B. (2015). Gender differences in responses to moral dilemmas. A process dissociation analysis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 41, 696–713.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerken, M., & Beebe, J. R. (2016). Knowledge in and out of contrast. Nous, 50, 133–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gosling, S. D., Rentfrow, P. J., & Swann, W. B., Jr. (2003). A very brief measure of the Big Five personality domains. Journal of Research in Personality, 37, 504–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holtzman, G. (2013). Do personality effects mean philosophy is intrinsically subjective? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 20, 27–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holtzman, G. S. (2016). Rejecting beliefs, or rejecting believers? On the importance and exclusion of women in philosophy. Hypatia, 31, 293–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1907). Pragmatism: A new name for some old philosophy, old ways of thinking: Popular lectures on philosophy. Longmans: Green.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2007). The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical explorations, 10, 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, W. (2007). The efficient assessment for need for cognition: K-NfC-S. Korean Journal of Consumer and Advertising Psychology, 8, 127–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, M., & Yuan, Y. (2015). No cross-cultural differences in the Gettier car case intuition: A replication study of Weinberg et al. 2001. Episteme, 12, 355–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livengood, J., Sytsma, J., Feltz, A., Scheines, R., & Machery, E. (2010). Philosophical temperament. Philosophical Psychology, 23, 313–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ludwig, K. (2007). The epistemology of thought experiments: First person versus third person approaches. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 128–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2017). Philosophy within its proper bounds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Stich, S. P., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., Struchiner, N., Sirker, S., Usui, N., & Hashimoto, T. (forthcoming a). Gettier across cultures. Nous. doi: 10.1111/nous.12110.

  • Machery, E., Stich, S. P., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., Struchiner, N., Sirker, S., Usui, N., & Hashimoto, T. (forthcoming b). Gettier was framed. In M. Mizumoto, S. Stich, & E. McCready (Eds.), Epistemology for the rest of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Nadelhoffer, T., Kvaran, T., & Nahmias, E. (2009). Temperament and intuition: A commentary on Feltz and Cokely. Consciousness and Cognition, 18, 351–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J., Juan, V. S., & Mar, R. A. (2013). Lay denial of knowledge for justified true beliefs. Cognition, 129, 652–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., Machery, E., Stich, S. P., Alai, M., Angelucci, A., Berniunas, R., Buchtel, E. E., Chatterjee, A., Cheon, H., Cho, I.-R., Cohnitz, D., Cova, F., Dranselka, V., Lagos, A. E., Ghadakpour, L., Grinberg, M., Hannikainen, I., Hashimoto, T., Horowitz, A., Hristova, E., Jraissati, Y., Kadreva, V., Karasawa, K., Kim, H., Kim, Y., Lee, M., Mauro, C., Mizumoto, M., Moruzzi, S., Olivola, C. Y., Ornelas J., Osimani, B., Romero, C., Rosas Lopez, A., Sangoi, M., Sereni, A., Songhorian, S., Sousa, P., Struchiner, N., Tripodi, V., Usui, N., Vazquez del Mercado, A., Volpe, G., Vosperichian, H. A., Zhang, X., & Zhu, J. (forthcoming). Nothing at stake in knowledge. Nous.

  • Sartwell, C. (1991). Knowledge is merely true belief. American Philosophical Quarterly, 28, 157–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seyedsayamdost, H. (2015). On gender and philosophical intuition: Failure of replication and other negative results. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 642–673.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shafir, E. (1994). Uncertainty and the difficulty of thinking through disjunctions. Cognition, 50, 403–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shope, R. K. (1983). The analysis of knowing: A decade of research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starmans, C., & Friedman, O. (2012). The folk conception of knowledge. Cognition, 124, 272–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmans, C., & Friedman, O. (2013). Taking “know” for an answer: A reply to Nagel, San Juan, and Mar. Cognition, 129, 662–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (forthcoming). Explanations of the gender gap in philosophy. Philosophy Compass.

  • Thompson, M. M., Naccarato, M. E., Parker, K. C. H., & Moskowitz, G. (2001). The Personal Need for Structure (PNS) and Personal Fear of Invalidity (PFI) scales: Historical perspectives, present applications and future directions. In G. Moskowitz (Ed.), Cognitive social psychology: The Princeton symposium on the legacy and future of social cognition (pp. 19–39). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J., Buckwalter, W., & Blouw, P. (2015). Knowledge and luck. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 22, 378–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1981). The framing of decisions and the psychology of choice. Science, 211, 453–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2003). What good are counterexamples? Philosophical Studies, 115, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., Alexander, J., Gonnerman, C., & Reuter, S. (2012). Restrictionism and reflection: Challenge deflected, or simply redirected? The Monist, 95, 200–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colaço, D., Kneer, M., Alexander, J., & Machery, E. (ms). On second thought: A refutation of the reflection defense.

  • Mizumoto, M., Stich, S. P., & McCready, E. (Eds.), Epistemology for the rest of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This publication was made possible through the support of a grant from the Fuller Theological Seminary/Thrive Center in concert with the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views of the Fuller Thrive Center or the John Templeton Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Edouard Machery.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D. et al. The Gettier Intuition from South America to Asia. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 34, 517–541 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0113-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0113-y

Keywords

Navigation