Advertisement

Animal life and mind in Hobbes’s philosophy of nature

  • Emre EbetürkEmail author
Original Paper
  • 35 Downloads

Abstract

This paper explores Thomas Hobbes’s account of animal life and mind. After a critical examination of Hobbes’s mechanistic explanation of operations of the mind such as perception and memory, I argue that his theory derives its strength from his idea of the dynamic interaction of the body with its surroundings. This dynamic interaction allows Hobbes to maintain that the purposive disposition of the animal is not merely an upshot of its material configuration, but an expression of its distinctive bodily history. In support of Hobbes, I show how this is complemented by his account of the unity and continuity of the animal body in terms of a unification through the self-preserving drive that originates in perception. Nonetheless, I argue that Hobbes’s philosophy of animal life and mental faculties is hindered by a kind of epiphenomenalist perspective that is embedded in his materialist framework, and this perspective leaves the status of ideas and mental content unclear. I explain why Hobbes’s dynamic theory, founded upon the reciprocal determination of moving bodies, supports his idea of animal development and habituation while failing to account for the reflexivity of the mind.

Keywords

Hobbes Sensation Perception Memory Phantasm Animal life Conatus Vital motion Voluntary motion Epiphenomenalism 

References

  1. Barnouw, J. (1980). Hobbes’s causal account of sensation. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 18(2), 115–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bernstein, H. R. (1980). Conatus, Hobbes, and the young Leibnitz. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 11(1), 25–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Brandt, F. (1928). Thomas Hobbes’s mechanical conception of nature. Copenhagen: Levin & Munksgaard.Google Scholar
  4. Descartes, R. (1985). The philosophical writings of descartes (Vol. 1) (J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, and D. Murdoch, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Duncan, S. (2010). Leibniz on Hobbes’s materialism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(1), 11–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Duncan, S. (2012). Debating materialism: Cavendish, Hobbes, and more. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 29(4), 391–409.Google Scholar
  7. Engel, S. M. (1962). Analogy and equivocation in Hobbes. Philosophy, 37(142), 326–335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Frost, S. (2005). Hobbes and the matter of self-consciousness. Political Theory, 33(4), 495–517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Garau, R. (2016). Springs, nitre, and conatus. The role of the heart in Hobbes’s physiology and animal locomotion. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 24(2), 231–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gert, B. (1965). Hobbes, mechanism, and egoism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 15(61), 341–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gert, B. (1996). Hobbes’s psychology. In T. Sorell (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Hobbes (pp. 157–174). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gert, B. (2010). Hobbes. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  13. Herbert, G. B. (1989). Thomas Hobbes: The unity of scientific and moral wisdom. Vancouver: UBC Press.Google Scholar
  14. Hobbes, T. (1839–1845). The English Works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury in 11 volumes. W. Molesworth (Ed.). London: John Bohn. [EW-IVII].Google Scholar
  15. Jonas, H. (1985). The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  16. Jonas, H. (2001). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Karskens, M. J. J. (1982). In J. G. van der Bend (Ed.), Hobbes, Thomas: His view of man. Proceedings of the Hobbes symposium at the International School of Philosophy in the Netherlands (pp. 45–56). Amsterdam: Rodopi B.V.Google Scholar
  18. Leijenhorst, C. (2002). The mechanisation of aristotelianism: The Late Aristotelian setting of Thomas Hobbes’s Natural Philosophy. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  19. Leijenhorst, C. (2004). Hobbes and the Galilean Law of Free Fall. In C. R. Palmerino & J. M. M. H. Thijssen (Eds.), The reception of the Galilean Science of Motion in seventeenth-century Europe (pp. 165–184). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Leijenhorst, C. (2007). Sense and nonsense about sense: Hobbes and the aristotelians on sense perception and imagination. In P. Springborg (Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes’s Leviathan (pp. 82–108). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Lemetti, J. (2013). Sensation and perception. In S. A. Lloyd (Ed.), The Bloomsbury companion to Hobbes (pp. 112–115). London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  22. Lott, T. L. (1982). Hobbes’s mechanistic psychology. In J. G. van der Bend (Ed.), Hobbes, Thomas: His view of man. Proceedings of the Hobbes symposium at the International School of Philosophy in the Netherlands (pp. 63–76). Amsterdam: Rodopi B.V.Google Scholar
  23. Medina, J. (2013). Physiologie mécaniste et mouvement cardiaque: Hobbes, Harvey et Descartes. In J. Berthier, N. Dubos, A. Milanese, & J. Terrel (Eds.), Lectures de Hobbes (pp. 133–164). Paris: Ellipses.Google Scholar
  24. Peters, R. S., & Tajfel, H. (1957). Hobbes and Hull—Metaphysicians of behaviour. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 8(29), 30–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Sepper, D. L. (1988). Imagination, phantasms, and the making of Hobbesian and Cartesian science. The Monist, 71(4), 526–542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Sorell, T. (1986). Hobbes (arguments of the philosophers). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  27. Toto, F. (2015). Lʼindividualità dei corpi. Milano: Mimesis.Google Scholar
  28. Toto, F. (2016). Individuo, potere e relazione in Thomas Hobbes. La Società degli Individui (LA), 55, 143–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Watkins, J. W. N. (1955). Philosophy and politics in Hobbes. The Philosophical Quarterly, 5(9), 125–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Watkins, J. W. N. (1973). Hobbes’s system of ideas: A study in the political significance of philosophical theories. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
  31. Wilson, C. (1997). Motion, sensation, and the infinite: the lasting impression of Hobbes on Leibniz. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 5(2), 339–351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.BerlinGermany

Personalised recommendations