Life as Adaptive Capacity: Bringing New Life to an Old Debate
Abstract
Whatever we take “life” to mean, it must involve an attempt to describe the objective reality beyond scientists’ biases. Traditionally, this is thought to involve comparing our scientific categories to “natural kinds.” But this approach has been tainted with an implicit metaphysics, inherited from Aristotle, that does not fit biological reality. In particular, we must accept that biological categories will never be specifiable in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions or shared underlying physical structures that produce clean boundaries. Biology blurs all lines and failure to embrace this unique feature has blocked attempts to reach consensus on the meaning of “life.” Thus, while the three classical accounts (thermodynamic, metabolic, and evolutionary) all fall short of offering a complete definition, their advocates fail to realize that they share the same view of life’s ultimate, functional hallmark: its uniquely rich adaptive capacity. I develop an account of life as adaptive capacity that sidesteps debates about the relative importance of specific mechanisms and the precise location of boundaries to bring the three classical accounts together under a shared conceptual framework.
Keywords
Adaptation Aristotle Complexity Definition Life Natural kindNotes
Acknowledgements
The ideas in this article were inspired by numerous conversations with too many colleagues to mention. However, extensive comments provided on an earlier draft by Carlos Mariscal and Erik Persson were especially helpful. Any deficiencies that remain are, of course, entirely the fault of the author.
References
- Adami C (2002) What is complexity? BioEssays 24:1085–1094CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Baross J (2007) The limits of organic life in planetary systems. National Academies Press, Washington DCGoogle Scholar
- Beatty J (1995) The evolutionary contingency thesis. In: Wolters G, Lennox J (eds) Concepts, theories and rationality in the biological sciences. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 45–81Google Scholar
- Bedau M (1996) The nature of life. In: Boden M (ed) The philosophy of artificial life. Oxford University Press, New York, pp 332–357Google Scholar
- Boyd R (1991) Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philos Stud 61(1/2):127–148CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Brandon R (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
- Brandon R, Antonovics J, Burian R et al (1994) Sober on Brandon on screening-off and the levels of selection. Philos Sci 61(3):475–486CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cavazzoni C, Chiarotti GL, Scandolo S et al (1999) Superionic and metallic states of water and ammonia at giant planet conditions. Science 283(5398):44–46CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chaisson E (2002) Cosmic evolution: the rise of complexity in nature. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
- Chyba C, Mcdonald GD (1995) Annu Rev Earth Planet Sci 23:15–249CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ćirković M, Bradbury R (2006) Galactic gradients, postbiological evolution and the apparent failure of SETI. New Astron 11(8):628–639CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cleland C (2012) Life without definitions. Synthese 185:125–144CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cleland C, Chyba C (2002) Defining "life." Orig Life Evol Bios 32:387–393CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cleland C, Chyba C (2007) Does "life" have a definition? In: Sullivan W, Baross JA (eds) Planets and life: the emerging science of astrobiology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 119–131Google Scholar
- Cleland C, Copley S (2005) The possibility of alternative microbial life on earth. Int J Astrobiol 4:165–173CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cleland C, Zerella M (2013) What is life? In: Kampourakis K (ed) The philosophy of biology. Springer, New York, pp 31–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Davies P (2011) The Eerie silence. Mariner Books, New YorkGoogle Scholar
- Donoghue M (1985) A critique of the biological species concept and recommendations for a phylogenetic alternative. Bryologist 88(3):172–181CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ereshefsky M (2009) Natural kinds in biology. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Taylor and Francis, https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/natural-kinds-in-biology/v-1. Accessed 1 Sept 17
- Fleischaker G (1990) Origins of life: an operational definition. Org Life Evol Biosph 20(2):127–137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Gould S (1989) Wonderful life. New York, NortonGoogle Scholar
- Joyce G, Deamer D, Fleischaker G (1994) Origins of life: the central concepts. Jones and Bartlett, BostonGoogle Scholar
- Korzeniewski B (2005) Confrontation of the cybernetic definition of living individual with the real world. Acta Biotheor 53:1–28CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Koshland D (2002) The seven pillars of life. Science 295:2215–2216CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lauder G, Tytell E (2006) Hydrodynamics of undulatory propulsion. In: Shadwick R, Lauder G (eds) Fish biomechanics. Fish Physiology, vol 23. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 425–468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Machery E (2011) Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life…and why you should as well. Synthese 185(1):145–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Mackie J (1965) Causes and conditions. Am Philos Q 12:245–265Google Scholar
- Margulis L, Sagan D (1995) What is life? Simon and Schuster, New YorkGoogle Scholar
- Mariscal C (2016) Universal biology: assessing universality from a single example. In: Dick S (ed) The impact of discovering life beyond earth. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 113–126Google Scholar
- Mayr E (2000) The biological species concept. In: Wheeler Q, Meier R (eds) Species concepts and phylogenetic history. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 17–29Google Scholar
- McKay C (1998) Life in the planetary context. In: Woodward C, Shull M, Thronson H (eds) Origins, ASP conference series, vol 148, pp 449–456Google Scholar
- Milligan T (2015) Nobody owns the moon. McFarland Publishing, JeffersonGoogle Scholar
- Mishler B, Brandon R (1987) Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept. Biol Philos 2(4):397–414CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Nixon K, Wheeler Q (1990) An amplification of the phylogenetic species concept. Cladistics 6(3):211–223CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Oliver J, Perry R (2006) Definitely life but not definitively. Orig Life Evol Bios 36:515–521CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Olson E (1997) The ontological basis of strong artificial life. Artif Life 3(1):29–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Persson E (2013) Philosophical aspects of astrobiology. In: Dunér D, Pathermore J, Persson E, Holmberg G (eds) The history and philosophy of astrobiology. Cambridge Scholars Press, Newcastle upon Tyne, pp 29–48Google Scholar
- Popa R (2004) Between necessity and probability. Springer, New YorkGoogle Scholar
- Prigogine I (1973) Can thermodynamics explain biological order. Impact Sci Soc 23(3):159–169Google Scholar
- Putnam H (1973) Meaning and reference. J Philos 70:699–711CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Reichenbach H (1956) The direction of time. University of Los Angeles Press, BerkeleyGoogle Scholar
- Rieppel O (2009) Species monophyly. J Zoolog Syst Evolut Res 48(1):1–8Google Scholar
- Schneider E, Sagan D (2005) Into the cool—energy flow, thermodynamics, and life. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
- Schrödinger E (1944) What is life—the physical aspect of the living cell. Cambridge University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
- Smith KC (1993) Marketing structuralism: reflections on the process structuralist critique of neo-darwinism. Rivista di Biologia/Biol Forum 86(3–4):578–579Google Scholar
- Smith KC (2014) Manifest complexity: a foundational ethics for astrobiology? Space Policy 30(4):209–214CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Smith KC (2016) Life is hard: countering definitional pessimism concerning the definition of life. Int J Astrobiol 15(4):277–289CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Szostak J (2012) Attempts to define life do not help to understand the origin of life. J Biomol Struc Dynam 29(4):599–600CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Toepfer G (2012) Teleology and its constitutive role for biology as the science of organized systems in nature. Stud Hist Philos Sci 43(1):113–119Google Scholar
- Trifonov E (2012) Definition of life: navigation through uncertainties. J Biomol Struc Dynam 29(4):647–650CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Wagner A (2013) Robustness and evolvability in living systems. Princeton University Press, PrincetonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Walker S, Davies P (2013) The algorithmic origins of life. J R Soc Interface. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2012.0869 Google Scholar
- Weaver W (1948) Science and complexity. Am Sci 36:536–544Google Scholar
- Zyga L (2016) Did the 40-year-old Viking experiment discover life on Mars? Phys.org, https://phys.org/news/2016-10-year-old-viking-life-mars.html. Accessed 30 Aug 2017