Essentialism, Vitalism, and the GMO Debate

Research Article
  • 14 Downloads

Abstract

There has been a long-standing opposition to genetically modified organisms (GMOs) worldwide. Some studies have tried to identify the deep-lying philosophical, conceptual as well as psychological motivations for this opposition. Philosophical essentialism, psychological essentialism, and vitalism have been proposed as possible candidates. I approach the plausibility of the claim that these notions are related to GMO opposition from a historical perspective. Vitalism and philosophical essentialism have been associated with anti-GMO stance on account of their purported hostility to species and organismic mutability. I show that vitalism has often been associated to various mutabilist theories, whereas the case for philosophical essentialism as motivating GMO opposition depends on the now discredited Essentialism Story that had constructed essentialism as a predominant view in pre-Darwinian science. Further, as philosophical essentialism taken seriously is incompatible with the reality of genetic engineering, it is unlikely to be a reason for opposition. Psychological essentialism, involving an instinctive repulsion from the practice of manipulating what is thought to be the essence of living beings, is a more likely reason for resistance to transgenesis. Yet even here, historical considerations are crucial. Not only lay people tend to essentialize genes, but scientists themselves can be shown to have been complicit in essentialist tendencies. From the advent of modern genetics, the imagery of the all-powerful genes, often depicted by scientists themselves metaphorically as material counterparts of the now obsolete vitalistic agent, has permeated the language of leading scientific figures, whose influence in shaping public opinion should not be downplayed. Enthusiasm for genetic engineering and the abhorrence from it might both derive from the same unrealistic image of the essential gene, the revision of which thus holding out the hope for transcending the present impasse of the GMO controversy.

Keywords

Genetically modified organisms GMOs Essentialism Vitalism Genetic engineering Essentialism Story 

References

  1. Amundson, R. (1998). Typology reconsidered: two doctrines on the history of evolutionary biology. Biology and Philosophy, 13(2), 153–177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Amundson, R. (2005). The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: the roots of evo-devo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Aristotle. (1933). In H. Tredennick (Ed.), Metaphysics. Cambridge MA – London: Harvard University Press – William Heinemann.Google Scholar
  4. Aristotle. (1963). In A. L. Peck (Ed.), The generation of animals. Cambridge MA – London: Harvard University Press – William Heinemann.Google Scholar
  5. Asprem E. (2015). How Schrödinger’s cat became a zombie: on the epidemiology of science-based representations in popular science and religious contexts. Method and Theory in the Study of Religion28(2), 113–140. Google Scholar
  6. Balme, D. M. (1972). Aristotle’s de Partibus Animalium and De Generatione Animalium I. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Balme, D. M. (1987). Aristotle’s biology was not essentialist. In A. Gotthelf & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Philsophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 291–312). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bawa, A. S., & Anilakumar, K. R. (2012). Genetically modified foods: safety, risks and public concerns—a review. Journal of Food Science and Technology, 50(6), 1035–1046.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Blancke, S., Breusegen, F., Jaeger, G., Braeckman, J., & Montagu, M. (2015). Fatal attraction: the intuitive appeal of GMO opposition. Trends in Plant Science, 20(7), 414–418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Bonny, S. (2003). Why are most Europeans opposed to GMOs? Factors explaining rejection in France and Europe. Electronic Journal of Biotechnology, 6(1), 50–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Davies, K. G. (2000). Creative tension: what links Aristotle, William Blake, Darwin and GM crops? Nature, 4, 135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Davies, K. G. (2001). What makes genetically modified organisms so distasteful? Trends in Biotechnology, 19(10), 424–427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Delbrück, M. (1971). Aristotle–totle–totle. In J. Monod & E. Borek (Eds.), Of microbes and life (pp. 50–55). New York – London: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Farber, P. L. (1976). The type-concept in zoology during the first half of the nineteenth century. Journal of the History of Biology, 9(1), 92–119.Google Scholar
  15. Gelman, S. A., & Rhodes, M. (2012). “Two thousand years of stasis:” How psychological essentialism impedes evolutionary understanding. In K. S. Rosengren et al. (Eds.), Evolution challenges: integrating research and practice about evolution (pp. 3–21). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Giglioni, G. (2013). Jean-Baptiste Lamarck and the place of irritability in the history of life and death. In S. Normandin & C. T. Wolfe (Eds.), Vitalism and the scientific image in post-enlightenment life science, 1800–2010 (pp. 19–50). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Gilbert, W. (1992). A vision of the grail. In D. J. Kevles & L. Hood (Eds.), The code of codes: scientific and social issues in the human genome project (pp. 83–97). Cambridge MA – London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Goodwin, B. C. (2006). Developmental emergence, genes, and responsible science. In E. M. Neumann-Held & C. Rehmann-Sutter (Eds.), Genes in development: re-reading the molecular paradigm (pp. 337–348). Durham – London: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Greene, J. C. (1959). The death of Adam: evolution and its impact on Western thought. Ames: Iowa State University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Hunter, G. K. (2000). Vital forces: the discovery of the molecular basis of life. San Diego: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  21. Jayaraman, K., & Jia, H. (2012). GM phobia spreads in South Asia. Nature Biotechnology, 30(11), 1017–1019.Google Scholar
  22. Jacob, F., & Monod, J. (1961). Genetic regulatory mechanisms in the synthesis of proteins. Journal of Molecular Biology, 3(3), 318–354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Judson, H. F. (1995). The eighth day of creation: makers of the revolution in biology. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  24. Keller, E. F. (2000). The century of the gene. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Lamarck, J. B. (1984). Zoological philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  26. Lennox, J. G. (1987). Kinds, forms of kinds, and the more and the less in Aristotle’s biology. In A. Gotthelf & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophicsal issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 339–359). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Lennox, J. G. (2001). Are Aristotelian species eternal? In J. G. Lennox (Ed.), Aristotle’s philosophy of biology: studies in the origins of life sciences (pp. 131–159). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Mabaya, E., Fulton, J., Simiyu-Wafukho, S., & Nang’ayo, F. (2015). Factors influencing adoption of genetically modified crops in Africa. Development Southern Africa, 32(5), 577–591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Mayr, E. (1959). Darwin and the evolutionary theory in biology. In B. J. Meggers (Ed.), Evolution and anthropology: a centennial appraisal (pp. 1–10). Washington D. C: Anthropological society of Washington.Google Scholar
  30. Mayr, E. (1976). Evolution and the diversity of life: selected essays. Cambridge MA – London: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
  31. Mayr, E. (1968). Theory of biological classification. Nature, 220, 545–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Mayr, E. (1992). Species concepts and their application. In M. Ereshefsky (Ed.), The units of evolution: essays on the nature of species (pp. 15–26). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  33. Mayr, E. (1997). This is biology: the science of the living world. Cambridge MA – London: Belknap Press.Google Scholar
  34. Moss, L. (1992). A kernel of truth? On the reality of the genetic program. Proceedings in the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association., 1, 335–348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Moss, L. (2003). What genes can’t do. Cambridge MA – London: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  36. Murphy, D. (2007). Plant breeding and biotechnology: societal context and the future of agriculture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Müller-Wille, S. (1999). Botanik und weltweiter Handel. Zur Begründung eines natürlichen Systems der Pflanzen durch Carl von Linné (1707–78), Studien zur Theorie der Biologie, Band 3. Berlin: VWB.Google Scholar
  38. Nelkin, D., & Lindee, S. M. (1995). The DNA mystique: the gene as a cultural icon. New York: W. H. Freeman.Google Scholar
  39. Oyama, S. (2000). The ontogeny of information: developmental systems and evolution, 2nd ed. Durham NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
  40. Pew Research Center (2015). Public and scientists’ views on science and society. http://www.pewinternet.org/2015/01/29/public-and-scientists-views-on-science-and-society/. Accessed 7 July 2016.
  41. Powers, J. (2013). Finding Ernst Mayr’s Plato. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 44(4), 714–723.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Robert, J. S. (2004). Embryology, epigenesis, and evolution: taking development seriously. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Ross, D. (1923/2005). Aristotle. London – New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  44. Richards, R. J. (2002). The romantic conception of life: science and philosophy in the age of Goethe. Chicago – London: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Sarkar, S. (2005). Molecular models of life: philosophical papers on molecular biology. Cambridge, MA – London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  46. Sarkar, S. (2006). From genes as determinants to DNA as resource. In E. M. Neumann-Held & C. Rehmann-Sutter (Eds.), Genes in development: re-reading the molecular paradigm (pp. 77–95). Durham – London: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Sapp, J. (1987). Beyond the gene: cytoplasmic inheritance and the struggle for authority in genetics. New York – Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Schrödinger, E. (1944/1992). What is life? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Scott, S. E., Inbar, Y., & Rozin, P. (2016). Evidence for absolute moral opposition to genetically modified food in the United States. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 11(3), 311–324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Shtulmann, A., & Schulz, L. (2008). The relation between essentialist beliefs and evolutionary reasoning. Cognitive Science, 32, 1049–1062.Google Scholar
  51. Szántó, V. (2015). Vitalistic approaches of life in early modern England. Theory of Science / Teorie Vědy, 38(2), 209–230.Google Scholar
  52. Turner, J. S. (2013). Homeostasis and the forgotten vitalist roots of adaptation. In S. Normandin & C. T. Wolfe (Eds.), Vitalism and the scientific image in post-Enlightenment life science, 1800–2010 (pp. 271–291). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Wade, N. (2000). Scientists complete rough draft of human genome. The New York Times, 26 June. https://partners.nytimes.com/library/national/science/062600sci-human-genome.html Accessed 7 July 2016.
  54. Wilkins, J. S. (2009). Species: history of an idea. Berkeley – Los Angeles – London: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  55. Wilkins, J. S. (2010). What is a species? Essences and generation. Theory of Bioscience, 129(2), 141–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Winsor, M. P. (2003). Non-essentialist methods in pre-Darwinian taxonomy. Biology and Philosophy, 18(3), 387–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Winsor, M. P. (2006a). Linnaeus’s biology was not essentialist. Annals of the Missouri Botanical Garden, 93(1), 2–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Winsor, M. P. (2006b). The creation of the essentialism story: an exercise in metahistory. History and Philosophy of Science, 28(2), 149–174.Google Scholar
  59. Wolfe, C. T., & Terada, M. (2008). The animal economy as object and program in Montpellier vitalism. Science in Context, 21(4), 537–579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Zirkle, C. (1959). Species before Darwin. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 103(5), 636–644.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute of PhilosophyEötvös Loránd UniversityBudapestHungary

Personalised recommendations