Philosophy & Technology

, Volume 24, Issue 2, pp 115–136 | Cite as

Imaging Technology and the Philosophy of Causality

Research Article

Abstract

Russo and Williamson (Int Stud Philos Sci 21(2):157–170, 2007) put forward the thesis that, at least in the health sciences, to establish the claim that C is a cause of E, one normally needs evidence of an underlying mechanism linking C and E as well as evidence that C makes a difference to E. This epistemological thesis poses a problem for most current analyses of causality which, in virtue of analysing causality in terms of just one of mechanisms or difference making, cannot account for the need for the other kind of evidence. Weber (Int Stud Philos Sci 23(2):277–295, 2009) has suggested to the contrary that Giere’s probabilistic analysis of causality survives this criticism. In this paper, we look in detail at the case of medical imaging technology, which, we argue, supports the thesis of Russo and Williamson, and we respond to Weber’s suggestion, arguing that Giere’s account does not survive the criticism.

Keywords

Causality Causation Difference making Mechanism Medical imaging 

References

  1. Barrett, H. H., & Swindell, W. (1981). Radiological imaging (Vol. 2). New York: Academic.Google Scholar
  2. Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (2010). Neuroimaging as a tool for functionally decomposing cognitive processes. In: Hanson, S.J. & Bunzl, M. (Eds.), Foundational issues in human brain mapping (pp. 241–262). Cambridge: MIT.Google Scholar
  3. Broadbent, A. (2010). Inferring causation in epidemiology: Mechanisms, black boxes, and contrasts. In: Illari, P. M., Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (Eds.), Causality in the sciences (pp. 45–69). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Cho, Z., Jones, J., & Singh, M. (1993). Foundations Of medical imaging. New York: Wiley-Interscience.Google Scholar
  5. Clarke, B. (2010). Causality in medicine with particular reference to the viral causation of cancers. Ph.D. thesis, Department of Science and Technology Studies. London: University College London.Google Scholar
  6. Davidson, D. (1989). Cardiovascular effects of alcohol. Western Journal of Medicine, 151, 430–439.Google Scholar
  7. Demirovic, J., Nabulsi, A., Folsom, A. R., Carpenter, M. A., Szklo, M., Sorlie, P. D., et al. (1993). Alcohol consumption and ultrasonographically assessed carotid artery wall thickness and distensibility. Circulation, 88, 2787–2793.Google Scholar
  8. Doby, T., & Alker, G. (1997). Origins and development of medical imaging. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Duchene, C., Olindo, S., Chausson, N., Jeannin, S., Cohen-Tenoudji, P., & Smadja, D. (2010). Cannabis-induced cerebral and myocardial infarction in a young woman. Revue neurologique, 166(4), 438–442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Farrell, B. (2010). Can’t get you out of my head: The human rights implications of using brain scans as criminal evidence. Interdisciplinary Journal of Human Rights Law, 4, 89–95.Google Scholar
  11. Giere, R. (1979). Understanding scientific reasoning. Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace, fourth (1997) edition.Google Scholar
  12. Gillies, D. A. (2011). The Russo–Williamson thesis and the question of whether smoking causes heart disease. In: Illari, P. M., Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (Eds.), Causality in the sciences (pp. 110–125). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Hendee, W., & Ritenour, E. R. (2002). Medical imaging physics. New York: Wiley-Liss, fourth (2002) edition.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Howick, J. (2010). Exposing the vanities—and a qualified defence—of mechanistic reasoning in clinical decision-making (unpublished manuscript).Google Scholar
  15. Illari, P. M. (2011). Disambiguating the Russo-Williamson thesis. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science (in press).Google Scholar
  16. Kelves, B. (1997). Naked to the bone: Medical imaging in the twentieth century. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Lakshman, R., Garige, M., Gong, M., Leckey, L., Varatharajalu, R., & Zakhari, S. (2010). Is alcohol beneficial or harmful for cardioprotection? Genes and Nutrition, 5, 111–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Leibovici, L. (2001). Effects of remote, retroactive intercessory prayer on outcomes in patients with bloodstream infection: Randomised controlled trial. British Medical Journal, 323, 1450–1451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Raichle, M., & Mintun, M. (2006). Brain work and brain imaging. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 29, 449–476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Rimm, E. B., Klatsky, A., Grobbee, D., & Stampfer, M. J. (1996). Review of moderate alcohol consumption and reduced risk of coronary heart disease: is the effect due to beer, wine, or spirits? British Medical Journal, 312, 731–736.Google Scholar
  23. Roberts, G. M., & Garavan, H. (2010). Evidence of increased activation underlying cognitive control in ecstasy and cannabis users. NeuroImage, 52(2), 429–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Russo, F. & Williamson, J. (2007). Interpreting causality in the health sciences. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 21(2), 157–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (2011). Generic versus single-case causality: the case of autopsy. European Journal for Philosophy of Science (in press).Google Scholar
  26. Steinberg, D., Pearson, T. A., & Kuller, L. H. (1991). Alcohol and atherosclerosis. Annals of Internal Medicine, 114, 967–976.Google Scholar
  27. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. van Hell, H., Vink, M., Ossewaarde, L., Jager, G., Kahn, R., & Ramsey, N. (2010). Chronic effects of cannabis use on the human reward system: An fMRI study. European neuropsychopharmacology, 20(3), 153–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Vliegenthart, R., Oei, H.-H. S., van den Elzen, A. P. M., van Rooij, F. J. A., Hofman, A., Oudkerk, M., et al. (2004). Alcohol consumption and coronary calcification in a general population. Archives of Internal Medicine, 164, 2355–2360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Webb, S. (1990). From the watching of shadows: The origins of radiological tomography. Bristol: Institute of Physics.Google Scholar
  31. Weber, E. (2007). Social mechanisms, causal inference, and the policy relevance of social science. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 30(3), 348–359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Weber, E. (2009). How probabilistic causation can account for the use of mechanistic evidence. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 23(3), 277–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Williamson, J. (2009). Probabilistic theories. In Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., and Menzies, P., (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 185–212). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Williamson, J. (2011). Mechanistic theories of causality. Philosophy Compass (in press).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy, SECLUniversity of KentCanterburyUK

Personalised recommendations