European Journal for Philosophy of Science

, Volume 4, Issue 3, pp 385–408 | Cite as

The epistemic account of ceteris paribus conditions

Original paper in Formal Epistemology

Abstract

The paper focuses on interpreting ceteris paribus conditions as normal conditions. After discussing six basic problems for the explication of normal conditions and seven interpretations that do not well solve those problems I turn to what I call the epistemic account. According to it the normal is, roughly, the not unexpected. This is developed into a rigorous constructive account of normal conditions, which makes essential use of ranking theory and in particular allows to explain the phenomenon of multiply exceptional conditions. Finally, this static account is extended to a schematic dynamic model of how we may learn about those normal and (multiply) exceptional conditions.

Keywords

Ceteris paribus laws Normal conditions Multiple exceptionality Conditional belief Ranking theory 

References

  1. Adams, E. W. (1975). The Logic of Conditionals. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Canfield, J., & Lehrer, K. (1961). Note on Prediction and Induction. Philosophy of Science, 28, 204–211.Google Scholar
  3. Carnap, R. (1956). The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts. In H. Feigl & M. Scriven (Eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science (Vol. I, pp. 38–76). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  4. Cartwright, N. (1983). How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s Capacities and Their Measurement. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  6. Cohen, L. J. (1977). The Probable and the Provable. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Earman, J., & Roberts, J. (1999). Ceteris Paribus, There is No Problem of Provisos. Synthese, 118, 439–478.Google Scholar
  8. Edgington, D. (1995). On Conditionals. Mind, 104, 235–327.Google Scholar
  9. Fodor, J. A. (1991). You Can Fool Some of the People All the Time, Every Else Being Equal: Hedged Laws and Psychological Explanations. Mind, 100, 19–34.Google Scholar
  10. Gärdenfors, P. (1981). An Epistemic Approach to Conditionals. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18, 203–211.Google Scholar
  11. Gillies, A. S. (2004). New Foundations for Epistemic Change. Synthese, 138, 1–48.Google Scholar
  12. Goldszmidt, M., & Pearl, J. (1996). Qualitative Probabilities for Default Reasoning, Belief Revision, and Causal Modeling. Artificial Intelligence, 84, 57–112.Google Scholar
  13. Hempel, C. G. (1988). Provisoes: A Problem Concerning the Inferential Function of Scientific Theories. Erkenntnis, 28, 147–164.Google Scholar
  14. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and Belief. New York: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Kaila, E. (1941). Über den physikalischen Realitätsbegriff. Acta Philosophica Fennica, 3, 33–34.Google Scholar
  16. Kern-Isberner, G., &, Thimm, M. (2012). A Ranking Semantics for First-Order Conditionals, in: L. De Raedt et al. (eds.) ECAI 2012, Open Access, IOS Press, pp. 456-461.Google Scholar
  17. Lange, M. (2002). Who’s Afraid of Ceteris Paribus Laws? Or: How I Learned to Stopped Worrying and Love Them. Erkenntnis, 57, 407–423.Google Scholar
  18. Mott, P. (1992). Fodor and Cetris Paribus Laws. Mind, 101, 335–346.Google Scholar
  19. Pietroski, P., & Rey, G. (1995). When Other Things Aren’t Equal: Saving Ceteris Paribus Laws from Vacuity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46, 81–110.Google Scholar
  20. Reiter, R. (1980). A Logic for Default Reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 13, 81–132.Google Scholar
  21. Reutlinger, A., Schurz, G., Hüttemenn, A. (2011). Ceteris Paribus Laws, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ceteris-paribus/
  22. Schiffer, S. (1991). Ceteris Paribus Laws. Mind, 100, 1–17.Google Scholar
  23. Schurz, G. (2001). What is ‘Normal’? An Evolution-Theoretic Foundation of Normic Laws and Their Relation to Statistical Normality. Philosophy of Science, 28, 476–497.Google Scholar
  24. Schurz, G. (2002). Ceteris Paribus Laws: Classification and Deconstruction. Erkenntnis, 57, 351–372.Google Scholar
  25. Shackle, G. L.S. (1969). Decision, Order, and Time in Human Affairs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd ed.Google Scholar
  26. Silverberg, A. (1996). Psychological Laws and Non-Monotonic Logic. Erkenntnis, 44, 199–224.Google Scholar
  27. Spohn, W. (2002). Laws, Ceteris Paribus Conditions, and the Dynamics of Belief. Erkenntnis 57, 373-394; also in: J. Earman, C. Glymour, S. Mitchell (eds.), Ceteris Paribus Laws, Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2002, pp. 97-118Google Scholar
  28. Spohn, W. (2012). The Laws of Belief. Ranking Theory and Its Philosophical Applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Spohn, W. (2013). A Ranking-Theoretic Approach to Conditionals. Cognitive Science, 37, 1074–1106.Google Scholar
  30. Stegmüller, W. (1969). Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, Band I, Wissenschaftliche Erklärung und Begründung. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Stegmüller, W. (1970). Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, Band II, Theorie und Erfahrung, 1. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  32. Strößner, C. (2013). Die Logik der Normalität: Untersuchungen zur Semantik von Normalitätsurteilen. Berlin: de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  33. Veltman, F. (1996). Defaults in Update Semantics. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25, 221–261.Google Scholar
  34. Woodward, J. (2002). There Is No Such Thing as a Ceteris Paribus Law. Erkenntnis, 57, 303–328.Google Scholar
  35. Woodward, J. (2003). Making Things Happen. A Theory of Causal Explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of KonstanzKonstanzGermany

Personalised recommendations