European Journal for Philosophy of Science

, Volume 2, Issue 2, pp 161–179

Carnap on concept determination: methodology for philosophy of science

Original paper in Philosophy of Science

Abstract

Recent criticisms of intuition from experimental philosophy and elsewhere have helped undermine the authority of traditional conceptual analysis. As the product of more empirically informed philosophical methodology, this result is compelling and philosophically salutary. But the negative critiques rarely suggest a positive alternative. In particular, a normative account of concept determination—how concepts should be characterized—is strikingly absent from such work. Carnap's underappreciated theory of explication provides such a theory. Analyses of complex concepts in empirical sciences illustrates and supports this claim, and counteracts the charge explication is only suitable for highly mathematical, axiomatic contexts. Explication is also defended against the influential criticism it is “philosophically unilluminating”.

Keywords

Explication Carnap Strawson Definition Methodology Precision Ecological stability Meaning Concepts 

References

  1. Belnap, N. (1993). On rigorous definitions. Philosophical Studies, 72, 115–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bishop, M., & Trout, J. D. (2005). The pathologies of standard analytic philosophy. Noûs, 39, 696–714.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Carnap, R. ([1932], 1959). The elimination of metaphysics through logical analysis of language. In A. J. Ayer (Ed.), Logical positivism (pp. 60–81). Glencoe: Free.Google Scholar
  4. Carnap, R. ([1934], 1937). The logical syntax of language. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. (1947). Meaning and necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  6. Carnap, R. (1950). Logical foundations of probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  7. Carnap, R. (1955). Meaning and synonymy in natural languages. Philosophical Studies, 7, 33–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Carnap, R. (1963a). P. F. Strawson on linguistic naturalismk. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 933–940). Lasalle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  9. Carnap, R. (1963b). W. V. Quine on logical truth. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 915–921). Lasalle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  10. Carnap, R. (1963c). Intellectual autobiography. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 3–84). Lasalle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  11. Carnap, R. (1977). In A. Shimony (Ed.), Two essays on entropy. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  12. Carnap, R., & Bar-Hillel, Y. (1953), An outline of a theory of semantic information. Technical Report No. 247: Research Laboratory of Electronics, MIT.Google Scholar
  13. Chang, H. (2004). Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Crupi, V., Tentori, K., & Gonzalez, M. (2007). On Bayesian measures of evidential support: theoretical and empirical issues. Philosophy of Science, 74, 229–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Cummins, R. (1998). Reflections on reflective equilibrium. In M. R. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry (pp. 113–128). New York: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  16. Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Dowe, P. (2004). Causation and misconnections. Philosophy of Science, 71, 926–931.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Eagle, A. (2004). Twenty one arguments against propensity analyses of probability. Erkenntnis, 60, 371–416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Egerton, F. (1973). Changing concepts of the balance of nature. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 48, 322–350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Ereshefsky, M. (2001). The poverty of the Linnaean Hierarchy: A philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Frege, G. (1980). Foundations of arithmetic. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Goldman, A., & Pust, J. (1998). Philosophical theory and intuitional evidence. In M. R. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry (pp. 179–197). New York: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  23. Grice, H. and Strawson, S. (1956). “In Defense of a Dogma.” Philosophical Review, 65, 141-158.Google Scholar
  24. Griffiths, P., Machery, E., & Linquist, S. (2009). The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind and Machine, 24, 605–630.Google Scholar
  25. Harman, G. (1994). Doubts about conceptual analysis. In M. Michael & J. O’Leary-Hawthorne (Eds.), Philosophy in mind (pp. 43–48). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Hinrichsen, D., & Pritchard, A. (2005). Mathematical systems theory I: Modelling, state space analysis, stability and robustness. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  27. Hintikka, J. (1999). The emperor’s new intuitions. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 127–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary didn’t know. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 291–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defense of conceptual analysis. New York: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  30. Justus, J. (2006). Loop analysis and qualitative modeling: Merits and limitations. Biology and Philosophy, 21, 647–666.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Justus, J. (2008a). Complexity, Diversity, Stability. In S. Sarkar & A. Plutynski (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of biology (pp. 321–350). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  32. Justus, J. (2008b). Ecological and Lyapunov stability. Philosophy of Science, 75, 421–436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kingsland, S. (1995). Modeling nature: Episodes in the history of population ecology (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  34. Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (Eds.). (2008). Experimental philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Kot, M. (2001). Elements of mathematical ecology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Everything must go: Metaphysics naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Lehman, C. L., & Tilman, D. (2000). Biodiversity, stability, and productivity in competitive communities. The American Naturalist, 156, 534–552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Levin, J. (2004). The evidential status of philosophical intuition. Philosophical Studies, 121, 193–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Logofet, D. (1993). Matrices and graphs: Stability problems in mathematical ecology. Ann Arbor: CRC.Google Scholar
  40. Loomis, E., & Juhl, C. (2006). Explication. In S. Sarkar & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), The philosophy of science: An introduction (pp. 287–294). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  41. Lotka, A. J. (1925). Elements of mathematical biology. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
  42. Maher, P. (2007). Explication defended. Studia Logica, 86, 331–341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2003). Should we trust our intuitions?: Deflationary accounts of the analytic data. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103, 299–323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (2008). Concepts. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2008 edition) <http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/concepts>.
  45. Moore, G. E. (1942). A reply to my critics: Analysis. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore (pp. 660–667). Lasalle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  46. Muller, F. A. (2004). The implicit definition of the set-concept. Synthese, 138, 417–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Nichols, S. (2004). Folk concepts and intuitions: From philosophy to cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 514–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Norton, J. D. (1991). Thought experiments in Einstein’s work. In T. Horowitz & G. Massey (Eds.), Thought experiments in science and philosophy (pp. 129–148). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  49. Ramsey, W. (1998). Prototypes and conceptual analysis. In M. R. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry (pp. 161–178). New York: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  50. Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. B. (1975). Family resemblances: Studies in the internal structure of categories. Cognitive Psychology, 8, 382–439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 479–493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Salman, W. (1997). Causality and explanation: A reply to two critiques. Philosophy of Science, 64, 461–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Skyrms, B. (2010). Signals. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Sober, E. (1988). Reconstructing the past: Parsimony, evolution and inference. Cambridge: MIT.Google Scholar
  55. Sorensen, R. (1991). Vagueness and the desiderata for definition. In J. H. Fetzer, D. Shatz, & G. N. Schlesinger (Eds.), Definitions and definability: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 71–110). Boston: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2001). Causation, prediction, and search (2nd ed.). Cambridge: MIT.Google Scholar
  57. Stich, S. (1998). Reflective equilibrium, analytic epistemology and the problem of cognitive diversity. In M. R. DePaul & W. Ramsey (Eds.), Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry (pp. 95–112). New York: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  58. Strawson, P. F. (1963). Carnap’s views on constructed systems versus natural languages in analytic philosophy. In P. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 503–518). Lasalle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  59. Strawson, P. F. (1992). Analysis and metaphysics: An introduction to philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  60. Tilman, D. (1999). The ecological consequences of biodiversity: A search for general principles. Ecology, 80, 1455–1474.Google Scholar
  61. Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69, 212–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Walley, P. (1991). Statistical reasoning with imprecise probabilities. New York: Chapman and Hall.Google Scholar
  63. Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.Google Scholar
  64. Weinberg, J., Gonnerman, C., Buckner, C., & Alexander, J. (2010). Are philosophers expert intuiters? Philosophical Psychology, 23, 331–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentFlorida State University and University of SydneyTallahasseeUSA

Personalised recommendations