Advertisement

Consequences of a Functional Account of Information

Article
  • 15 Downloads

Abstract

This paper aims to establish several interconnected points. First, a particular interpretation of the mathematical definition of information, known as the causal interpretation, is supported largely by misunderstandings of the engineering context from which it was taken. A better interpretation, which makes the definition and quantification of information relative to the function of its user, is outlined. The first half of the paper is given over to introducing communication theory and its competing interpretations. The second half explores three consequences of the main thesis. First, a popular claim that the quantification of information in a signal is irrelevant for the meaning of that signal is exposed as fallacious. Second, a popular distinction between causal and semantic information is shown to be misleading, and I argue it should be replaced with a related distinction between natural and intentional signs. Finally, I argue that recent empirical work from microbiology and cognitive science drawing on resources of mathematical communication theory is best interpreted by the functional account. Overall, a functional approach is shown to be both theoretically and empirically well-supported.

Keywords

Mathematical communication theory Teleosemantics Sender-receiver framework Primitive content Rate-distortion theory 

Notes

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Ron Planer, two anonymous referees, and the editors for comments. Thanks also to Manolo Martínez for pointing me in the direction of rate-distortion theory. This research is supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program (RTP) Scholarship and Australian Research Council Laureate Fellowship Grant FL130100141.

References

  1. Adams, F. 2003. The informational turn in philosophy. Minds and Machines 13(4): 471–501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Artiga, M. 2016. Teleosemantic modeling of cognitive representations. Biology & Philosophy 31(4): 483–505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bar-Hillel, Y., and R. Carnap. 1953. Semantic information. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 4(14): 147–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bergstrom, C.T., and M. Rosvall. 2011. The transmission sense of information. Biology & Philosophy 26(2): 159–176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Burge, T. 2010. Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dall, S.R.X., L.-A. Giraldeau, O. Olsson, J.M. McNamara, and D.W. Stephens. 2005. Information and its use by animals in evolutionary ecology. Trends in Ecology & Evolution 20(4): 187–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Dennett, D.C. 1983. Intentional systems in cognitive ethology: The “Panglossian paradigm” defended. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6(3): 343–355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dennett, D. C. 2017. From bacteria to bach and back: The evolution of minds. Penguin UK.Google Scholar
  9. Donaldson-Matasci, M.C., C.T. Bergstrom, and M. Lachmann. 2010. The fitness value of information. Oikos 119(2): 219–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dretske, F. 1981. Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  11. Dretske, F. 1983. Précis of knowledge and the flow of information. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6(1): 55–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Dretske, F. 1988. Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Frank, S.A. 2012. Natural selection. V. How to read the fundamental equations of evolutionary change in terms of information theory. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 25(12): 2377–2396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Fresco, N. forthcoming. Functional information: A graded taxonomy of difference makers. Review of Philosophy and Psychology.Google Scholar
  15. Gallistel, C.R. 2003. Conditioning from an information processing perspective. Behavioural Processes 62(1–3): 89–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Godfrey-Smith, P., and K. Sterelny. 2016. Biological information. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Zalta E.N. Summer 2016 edition.Google Scholar
  17. Grice, H.P. 1957. Meaning. The Philosophical Review 66(3): 377–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hájek, A. 2007. The reference class problem is your problem too. Synthese 156(3): 563–585.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Harms, W.F. 2004. Primitive content, translation, and the emergence of meaning in animal communication. In Evolution of communication systems: A comparative approach, eds. Oller D.K. and Griebel U., 31–48. Cambridge, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Hartley, R.V.L. 1928. Transmission of information. Bell System Technical Journal 7(3): 535–563.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Huttegger, S.M. 2007. Evolutionary explanations of indicatives and imperatives. Erkenntnis 66(3): 409–436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hutto, D.D., and E. Myin. 2013. Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Iglesias, P.A. 2016. The use of rate distortion theory to evaluate biological signaling pathways. IEEE Transactions on Molecular, Biological and Multi-Scale Communications 2(1): 31–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Kelly, J.L. 1956. A new interpretation of information rate. Bell System Technical Journal 35(4): 917–926.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kraemer, D.M. 2015. Natural probabilistic information. Synthese 192 (9): 2901–2919.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Krebs, J.R., and R. Dawkins. 1984. Animal signals: Mind-reading and manipulation. In Behavioural ecology: An evolutionary approach, 2nd ed., eds. Krebs J.R. and Davies N.B., 380–402. Oxford, Blackwell Scientific.Google Scholar
  27. Lean, O.M. 2014. Getting the most out of Shannon information. Biology & Philosophy 29(3): 395–413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Lean, O.M. 2016. Biological information. Bristol: PhD thesis, University of Bristol.Google Scholar
  29. Lewis, D. 1969. Convention: A philosophical study. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  30. Lombardi, O., F. Holik, and L. Vanni. 2015. What is Shannon information? Synthese 193(7): 1983–2012.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. MacKay, D.M. 1969. Information, mechanism and meaning. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
  32. Mann, S. F. 2018. Attribution of information in animal interaction. Biological Theory.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-018-0299-5.
  33. Millikan, R.G. 1995. Pushmi-Pullyu representations. Philosophical Perspectives 9: 185–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Millikan, R.G. 2001. What has natural information to do with intentional representation? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 49: 105–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Millikan, R.G. 2013a. Natural information, intentional signs and animal communication. In Animal communication theory, ed. Stegmann U.E., 133–146. New York, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Millikan, R.G. 2013b. Reply to Rescorla. In Millikan and her critics, eds. Ryder D., Kingsbury J., and Williford K., 103–106. New York, Wiley.Google Scholar
  37. Millikan, R.G. 2017. Beyond concepts: Unicepts, language, and natural information. Oxford: OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Noel, A., Y. Fang, N. Yang, D. Makrakis, and A.W. Eckford. 2017. Using Game Theory for Real-Time Behavioral Dynamics in Microscopic Populations with Noisy Signaling.Google Scholar
  39. Owren, M.J., D. Rendall, and M.J. Ryan. 2010. Redefining animal signaling: Influence versus information in communication. Biology & Philosophy 25 (5): 755–780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Pfeifer, J. 2006. The use of information theory in biology: Lessons from social insects. Biological Theory 1(3): 317–330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Piccinini, G., and A. Scarantino. 2011. Information processing, computation, and cognition. Journal of Biological Physics 37(1): 1–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Price, H. 2008. Two readings of representationalism.Google Scholar
  43. Rathkopf, C. 2017. Neural information and the problem of objectivity. Biology & Philosophy 32(3): 321–336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Rescorla, M. 2013. Millikan on honeybee navigation and communication. In Millikan and her critics, eds. Ryder D., Kingsbury J., and Williford K., 87–102. Wiley.Google Scholar
  45. Rescorla, R.A. 1988. Pavlovian conditioning: It’s not what you think it is. The American Psychologist 43(3): 151–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Rouder, J.N., R.D. Morey, N. Cowan, and M. Pealtz. 2004. Learning in a unidimensional absolute identification task. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 11 (5): 938–944.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Sarkar, S. 2013. Information in animal communication: When and why does it matter? In Animal communication theory, ed. Stegmann U.E., 189–205. New York, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Scarantino, A. 2015. Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93(3): 419–443.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Shannon, C.E. 1948. A mathematical theory of communication (Part 1). Bell System Technical Journal 27(3): 379–423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Shannon, C.E. 1959. Coding theorems for a discrete source with a fidelity criterion. In Collected Papers, Wiley-IEEE Press, pp 325–350.Google Scholar
  51. Shannon, C.E., and W. Weaver. 1949. The mathematical theory of communication. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Google Scholar
  52. Shea, N., P. Godfrey-Smith, and R. Cao. 2017. Content in simple signalling systems. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, axw036.  https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axw036.
  53. Sims, C.R. 2016. Rate–distortion theory and human perception. Cognition 152: 181–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Skyrms, B. 2010. Signals: Evolution, learning, and information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Stegmann, U.E. (Ed.) 2013. Animal communication theory: Information and influence. Cambridge University Press: New York.Google Scholar
  56. Whyte, J.T. 1990. Success semantics. Analysis 50(3): 149–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.School of Philosophy, HC Coombs BuildingAustralian National UniversityCanberraAustralia

Personalised recommendations