Review of Philosophy and Psychology

, Volume 4, Issue 3, pp 391–406 | Cite as

The Proper Function of Artifacts: Intentions, Conventions and Causal Inferences

Article

Abstract

Designers’ intentions are important for determining an artifact’s proper function (i.e., its perceived real function). However, there are disagreements regarding why. In one view, people reason causally about artifacts’ functional outcomes, and designers’ intended functions become important to the extent that they allow inferring outcomes. In another view, people use knowledge of designers’ intentions to determine proper functions, but this is unrelated to causal reasoning, having perhaps to do with intentional or social forms of reasoning (e.g., authority). Regarding these latter social factors, researchers have proposed that designers’ intentions operate through a mechanism akin to social conventions, and that therefore both are determinants of proper function. In the current work, participants learned about an object’s creation, about social conventions for its use and about a specific episode where the artifact was used. The function implemented by the user could be aligned with the designer’s intended function, the social convention, both, or neither (i.e., an opportunistic use). Importantly, the use episode always resulted in an accident. Data show that the accident negatively affected proper function judgments and perceived efficiency for conventional and opportunistic functions, but not for designers’ intended functions. This is inconsistent with the view that designers’ intentions are conceptualized as causes of functional outcomes and with the idea that designers’ intentions and social conventions operate through a common mechanism.

References

  1. Ahn, W., C. Kalish, S. Gelman, D. Medin, C. Luhman, and S. Atran. 2001. Why essences are essential in the psychology of concepts. Cognition 82: 56–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Aunger, R. 2010. What’s special about human technology? Cambridge Journal of Economics 34: 115–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bloom, P. 1996. Intention, history, and artifact concepts. Cognition 60: 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bloom, P., and L. Markson. 1998. Intention and analogy in children’s naming of pictorial representations. Psychological Science 9: 200–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Casler, K., and D. Kelemen. 2005. Young children’s rapid learning about artifacts. Developmental Science 8: 472–480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Casler, K., T. Terziyan, and K. Greene. 2009. Toddlers view artifact function normatively. Cognitive Development 24: 240–247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chaigneau, S.E., L.W. Barsalou, and S. Sloman. 2004. Assessing the causal structure of function. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 133(4): 601–625.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chaigneau, S.E., R.D. Castillo, and L. Martinez. 2008. Creators’ intentions bias judgments of function independently from causal inferences. Cognition 109: 123–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cummins, R. 1975. Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy 72: 741–765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Defeyter, M.A., and T.P. German. 2003. Acquiring an understanding of design: Evidence form children’s insight problem solving. Cognition 89: 133–155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Defeyter, M.A., T.P. German, and S.E. Avons. 2007. Developmental changes in information central to artefact representation: Evidence from functional fluency tasks. Developmental Science 10: 538–546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Defeyter, M.A., J. Hearing, and T.P. German. 2009. A developmental dissociation between category and function judgments about novel artifacts. Cognition 110: 260–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dennett, D.C. 1990. The interpretation of texts, people and other artefacts. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50S: 177–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gelman, S.A., and P. Bloom. 2000. Children are sensitive to how an object was created when deciding what to name it. Cognition 76: 91–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. German, T.P., and M.A. Defeyter. 2000. Immunity to functional fixedness in young children. Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 7(4): 707–712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. German, T.P., and S.C. Johnson. 2002. Function and the origins of the design stance. Journal of Cognition and Development 3(3): 279–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. German, T.P., D. Truxaw, and M.A. Defeyter. 2007. The role of information about “convention”, “design”, and “goal” in representing artificial kinds. New Directions for Child and Adolescent Development 115: 69–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Gutheil, G., P. Bloom, N. Valderrama, and R. Freedman. 2004. The role of historical intuitions in children’s and adults’ naming of artifacts. Cognition 91(1): 23–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Kelemen, D., and S. Carey. 2007. The essence of artifacts: Developing the design stance. In Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation, ed. S. Laurence and E. Margolis, 212–230. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Lombrozo, T., and B. Rehder. 2012. Functions in biological kind classification. Cognitive Psychology 65: 457–485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Malt, B.C., and M.R. Paquet. 2012. The real deal: What judgments of really reveal about how people think about artifacts. Memory & Cognition. doi:10.3758/s13421-012-0270-9.Google Scholar
  22. Malt, B.C., and S.A. Sloman. 2007. Category essence or essentially pragmatic? Creator’s intention in naming and what’s really what. Cognition 105: 615–648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Matan, A., and S. Carey. 2001. Developmental changes within the core of artifact concepts. Cognition 78: 1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Oakes, L.M., and K.L. Madole. 2008. Function revisited: How infants construe functional features in their representation of objects. In Advances in child development and behavior, 36, ed. R. Kail, 135–185. San Diego: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Scheele, M. 2005. The proper use of artefacts. A philosophical theory of the social constitution of artefact functions. Leiden: Marcel Scheele.Google Scholar
  26. Scheele, M. 2006. Function and use of technical artefacts. The social conditions of function assignment. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37: 23–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Siegel, D., and M. Callanan. 2007. Artifacts as conventional objects. Journal of Cognition and Development 8: 183–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Tomasello, M. 1999. The cultural origins of human cognition. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Vaesen, K. 2012. The cognitive bases of human tool use. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35(4): 203–262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Vaesen, K., and M. van Amerongen. 2008. Optimality vs. intent: Limitations of Dennett’s artifact hermeneutics. Philosophical Psychology 21(6): 779–797.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Vermaas, P. E., M. Carrara, S. Borgo, and P. Garbacz 2011. The design stance and its artefacts. Synthese 1–22Google Scholar
  32. Whiten, A., V. Horner, and F. de Waal. 2005. Conformity to cultural norms of tool use in chimpanzees. Nature 437: 738–740.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Escuela de PsicologíaUniversidad Adolfo IbáñezPeñalolénChile
  2. 2.Universidad de TarapacáAricaChile

Personalised recommendations