Advertisement

Review of Philosophy and Psychology

, Volume 4, Issue 1, pp 135–152 | Cite as

Scaffolded Memory and Metacognitive Feelings

  • Santiago Arango-MuñozEmail author
Article

Abstract

Recent debates on mental extension and distributed cognition have taught us that environmental resources play an important and often indispensable role in supporting cognitive capacities. In order to clarify how interactions between the mind –particularly memory– and the world take place, this paper presents the “selection problem” and the “endorsement problem” as structural problems arising from such interactions in cases of mental scaffolding. On the one hand, the selection problem arises each time an agent is confronted with a cognitive problem, since she has to choose whether to solve it internally or externally. How does she choose? On the other hand, when confronted with the internally or externally retrieved solution to a cognitive task, the subject has to decide whether to endorse the information. How does the subject decide whether to endorse it or not? The last section proposes a solution to each problem in terms of metamemory and metacognitive feelings. Metamemory evaluates memory each time the subject is confronted with a memory task and elicits either a positive or negative metacognitive feeling that guides the decision.

Keywords

Selection Problem Semantic Memory External Resource Cognitive Problem Internal Memory 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgments

I would like to express my gratitude to Ken Aizawa, Anne-Sophie Brüggen, Koosha Eghbal, Christoph Michel, Joëlle Proust, Kevin Reuter, Camilo Uribe “el Pájaro”, Tobias Schlicht, Richard Stockle-Schobel, and Eric Schwitzgebel for their corrections, comments, and suggestions. I would specially like to thank the editors John Sutton and Kourken Michaelian, and also to two anonymous reviewers for their thorough corrections, comments, and suggestions to a previous draft. Their suggestions greatly improved this paper.

References

  1. Adams, F., and K. Aizawa. 2008. The bounds of cognition. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  2. Arango-Muñoz, S. 2011. Two levels of metacognition. Philosophia 39(1): 71–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Arango-Muñoz, S. (forthcoming). The Nature of Epistemic Feelings. Philosophical Psychology. Google Scholar
  4. Arango-Muñoz, S., Fernández-Cruz, A. L., and Volz, K. (in preparation). Monitoring one’s own Errors in the Number Bisection Task. Center for Integrative Neuroscience, Tübingen Universität, Germany.Google Scholar
  5. Bernecker, S. 2010. Memory: A philosophical study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Block, N. 1995. On a confusion about a function of consciousness. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18(2): 227–247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Brewer, W.F., and C. Sampaio. 2012. The metamemory approach to confidence: A test using semantic memory. Journal of Memory and Language 67: 59–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Carr, N. (2008). Is Google making us Stupid? The Atlantic, July/August. http://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2008/07/is-google-making-us-stupid/306868/ (Consulted 14Oct2012).
  9. Carruthers, P. 2009. How we know our own minds: The relationship between mindreading and metacognition. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 32: 1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Carruthers, P. 2011. The opacity of mind, an integrative theory of self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Chalmers, D. 2008. Foreword. In Supersizing the mind, ed. A. Clark, ix–xvi. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Clark, A. 2008. Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Clark, A., and D. Chalmers. 1998. The extended mind. Analysis 58: 10–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. de Sousa, R. 2008. Epistemic feelings. In Epistemology and emotions, ed. G. Brun, U. Doğuoğlu, and D. Kuenzle, 185–204. Hampshire: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  15. Dokic, J. 2012. Seeds of cognition. Noetic feelings and metacognition. In Foundations of metacognition, ed. M. Beran, J. Brandl, J. Perner, and J. Proust, 302–321. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Fetcher, L., and P. Carruthers. 2012. Metacognition and reasoning. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, Biological Sciences 367: 1366–1378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Finn, B. 2008. Framing effects on metacognitive monitoring and control. Memory and Cognition 36(4): 813–821.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. French, L., M. Garry, and K. Mori. 2008. You say tomato? Colaborative remembering leads to more false memories for intimate couples than for strangers. Memory 16(3): 262–273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Friedman, M.C., and A.D. Castel. 2011. Are we aware of our ability to forget? Metacognitive predictions of directed forgetting. Memory and Cognition 39: 1448–1456.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gilbert, D.T., D.S. Krull, and P.S. Malone. 1990. Unbelieving the unbelievable: some problems in the rejection of false information. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 59: 601–613.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Gilbert, D.T., R.W. Tafarodi, and P.S. Malone. 1993. You can’t not believe everything you read. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65: 221–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Halamish, V., S. McGillivray, and A.D. Castel. 2011. Monitoring one’s own forgetting in younger and older adults. Psychology and Aging 26: 631–635.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hart, J.T. 1965. Memory and the feeling-of-knowing experience. Journal of Educational Psychology 56: 208–216.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Hertwig, R., S.M. Herzog, L.J. Schooler, and T. Reimer. 2008. Fluency heuristic: A model of how the mind exploits a by-product of information retrieval. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 34(5): 1191–1206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Hookway, C. 2008. Epistemic immediacy, doubt and anxiety: A role for affective states epistemic evaluation. In Epistemology and emotions, ed. G. Brun, U. Doğuoğlu, and D. Kuenzle, 51–65. Hampshire: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  26. Johnson, M.K. 1997. Source monitoring and memory distortion. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 352(1362): 1733–1745.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Johnson, M.K. 2006. Memory and reality. The American Psychologist 61(8): 760–771.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Kahneman, D. 2011. Thinking fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
  29. Kalnikaité, V., and S. Whittaker. 2007. Software or wetware? Discovering when and why people use digital prosthetic memory. CHI 2007: Proceedings of the SIGCHI conference on Human factors in computing systems, 71–80. New York: ACM Press.Google Scholar
  30. Kelley, C.M., and S.D. Lindsay. 1993. Remembering mistaken for knowing: Ease of retrieval as a basis for confidence in answers to general knowledge questions. Journal of Memory and Language 32: 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Kirsh, D. 2004. Metacognition, distributed cognition and visual design. In Cognition, communication and education, ed. P. Gärdinfors and P. Johansson. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  32. Kirsh, D., and P. Maglio. 1992. Some epistemic benefits of action, Tetris, a case study. Proceedings of the Fourteenth Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  33. Koriat, A. 1993. How do we know that we know? The accessibility model of the feeling of knowing. Psychological Review 100: 609–639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Koriat, A. 2000. The feeling of knowing: some metatheoretical implications for consciousness and control. Consciousness and Cognition 9: 149–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Koriat, A. 2008. Subjective confidence in one’s answers: The consensuality principle. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 34(4): 945–959.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Koriat, A., and M. Goldsmith. 1996. Monitoring and control processes in the strategic regulation of memory. Psychological Review 103(3): 490–517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Koriat, A., R.A. Bjork, L. Sheffer, and S.K. Bar. 2004. Predicting one’s own forgetting: The role of experience-based and theory-based processes. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 133: 643–656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Krug, K. 2007. The relationship between confidence and accurancy: Current thoughts of the literature and a new area of research. Applied Psychology in Criminal Justice 3(1): 7–41.Google Scholar
  39. Loftus, E.F., J.A. Coan, and J.E. Pickrell. 1996. Manufacturing false memories using bits of reality. In Implicit memory and metacognition, ed. L.M. Reder, 195–220. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  40. Lovett, M.C., and J.R. Anderson. 1996. History of success and current context in problem solving. Combined influences on operator selection. Cognitive Psychology 31: 168–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Lovett, M.C., and C.D. Schunn. 1999. Task representations, strategy variability, and base-rate neglect. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 128: 107–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Luna, K., and B. Martín-Luengo. 2012. Confidence–Accuracy Calibration with General Knowledge and Eyewitness Memory Cued Recall Questions. Applied Cognitive Psychology 26(2): 289–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Mazzoni, G., A. Scoboria, and L. Harvey. 2010. Non-believed memories. Psychological Science 21(9): 1334–1340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Mercier, H., and D. Sperber. 2011. Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Brain and Behavioral Sciences 34: 57–111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Michaelian, K. 2011. Generative memory. Philosophical Psychology 24(3): 323–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Michaelian, K. 2012a. Metacognition and endorsement. Mind & Language 27(3): 284–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Michaelian, K. 2012b. Is external memory memory? Biological memory and extended mind. Consciousness and Cognition 21(3): 1154–1165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Michaelian, K. (2012c). (Social) metacognition and (self-)trust. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 1–34. doi 10.1007/s13164-012-0099-y
  49. Nelson, T.O. 1999. Cognition versus metacognition. In The nature of cognition, ed. R.J. Sternberg, 625–641. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  50. Nelson, T.O., and L. Narens. 1990. Metamemory: a theoretical framework and new findings. Psychology of Learning and Motivation 26: 125–173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Ong, W.J. 1982. Orality and literacy: The technologizing of the word. New York: Methuen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Oppenheimer, D. 2008. The secret life of fluency. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 12(6): 237–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Pannu, J.K., and A.W. Kaszniak. 2005. Metamemory experiments in neurological populations: A review. Neuropsychology Review 15: 105–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Payne, J.W., J.R. Bettman, and E.J. Johnson. 1988. Adaptive strategy selection in decision making. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory And Cognition 14: 534–552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Paynter, C.A., L.M. Reder, and P.D. Kieffaber. 2009. Knowing we know before we know: ERP correlates of initial feeling-of-knowing. Neuropsychologia 47: 796–803.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Perfect, T.J. 2004. The role of self-rated ability in the accuracy of confidence judgments in eyewitness memory and general knowledge. Applied Cognitive Psychology 18: 157–168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Piaget, J. 1951. Play, dreams, and imitation in childhood (L. Gattegno & F.M. Hodsen, Trans.). New York: Norton.Google Scholar
  58. Plato. 2011. Phaedrus. In Cambridge greek and latin classics, ed. H. Yunis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  59. Proust, J. 2007. Metacognition and metarepresentation: is a self-directed theory of mind a precondition for metacognition? Synthese 159: 271–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Proust, J. 2009a. It there a sense of agency of thought? In Mental actions and agency, ed. L. O’Brien and M. Soteriou. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  61. Proust, J. 2009b. The representational basis of brute metacognition: a proposal. In The philosophy of animal minds, ed. R. Lurz, 165–183. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Proust, J. 2012. Metacognition and mindreading, one or two functions. In Foundations of metacognition, ed. M. Beran, J. Brandl, J. Perner, and J. Proust, 234–251. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Proust, J. (forthcoming). Philosophy of metacognition, mental agency and mental awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  64. Reber, R., and N. Schwarz. 1999. Effects of perceptual fluency on judgments of truth. Consciousness and Cognition 8: 338–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Reber, R., and C. Unkelbach. 2010. The epistemic status of processing fluency as source for judgments of truth. Revue of Philosophy and Psychology 1: 563–581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Reder, L.M. 1987. Strategy selection in question answering. Cognitive Psychology 19(1): 90–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Reder, L.M. 1988. Strategic control of retrieval strategies. Psychology of Learning and Motivation 22: 227–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Reder, L.M. 1996. Implicit memory and metacognition. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  69. Reder, L.M., and F.E. Ritter. 1992. What determines initial feeling of knowing? Familiarity with question terms, not with the answer. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 18: 435–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Reder, L.M., and D.C. Schunn. 1996. Metacognition does not imply awareness: Strategy choice is governed by implicit learning and memory. In Implicit memory and metacognition, ed. L.M. Reder, 45–78. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  71. Robinson, M.D., J.T. Johnson, and F. Herndon. 1997. Reaction time and assessments of cognitive effort as predictors of eyewitness memory accuracy and confidence. Journal of Applied Psychology 82: 416–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Roth, P. (2012). An open letter to Wikipedia. The New Yorker, September 7th. http://www.newyorker.com/online/blogs/books/2012/09/an-open-letter-to-wikipedia.html (Consulted 10Sep2012)
  73. Schacter, D.L., and D.R. Addis. 2007. The cognitive neuroscience of constructive memory: Remembering the past and imagining the future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 362(1481): 773–786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Schneider, S.L., and S.K. Laurion. 1993. Do we know what we’ve learned from the news? Memory & Cognition 21: 198–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Schwartz, B. 2002. Tip-of-the-tongue states, phenomenology, mechanisms and lexical retrieval. London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  76. Schwartz, B., and J. Metcalfe. 2010. Tip-of-the-tongue (TOT) states: Retrieval, behavior, and experience. Memory and Cognition 39: 737–749.Google Scholar
  77. Sparrow, B., J. Liu, and D.M. Wegner. 2011. Google effects on memory: Cognitive consequences of having information at our fingertips. Science 333: 776–778.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Spehn, M.K., and L.M. Reder. 2000. The unconscious feeling of knowing: a commentary on Koriat’s paper. Consciousness and Cognition 9: 187–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Sperber, D., and D. Wilson. 1995. Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  80. Sperber, D., F. Clément, H. Heintz, O. Mascaro, H. Mercier, G. Origgi, and D. Wilson. 2010. Epistemic vigilance. Mind and Language 25(4): 359–393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Sterelny, K. 2004. Externalism, epistemic artefacts and the extended mind. In The externalist challenge, ed. R. Schantz, 239–254. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  82. Sterelny, K. 2010. Minds: Extended or scaffolded. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 9: 465–481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. Sutton, J. 2010. Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History, extended mind and the civilizing process. In The extended mind, ed. R. Menary, 189–225. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  84. Sutton, J., C.B. Harris, P.G. Keil, and A.J. Barnier. 2010. The psychology of memory, extended cognition, and socially distributed remembering. Phenomenonology and the Cognitive Sciences 9(4): 521–560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Thompson, V.A. 2009. Dual-process theories: A metacognitive perspective. In In two minds: Dual processes and beyond, eds. J. Evans and K. Frankish, 171–195. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  86. Thompson, V.A., J.A. Prowse, and G. Pennycook. 2011. Intuition, reason, and metacognition. Cognitive Psychology 63: 107–140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Walsh, M.M., and J.R. Anderson. 2009. The strategic nature of changing your mind. Cognitive Psychology 58: 416–440.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Wegner, D.M. 2002. The illusion of the conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  89. Whittlesea, B. 1993. Illusion of familiarity. Journal of Experimental Psychology 19(6): 1235–1253.Google Scholar
  90. Whittlesea, B., and L. Williams. 2001. Source of the feeling of familiarity: The discrepancy-attribution hypothesis. Journal of Experimental Psychology 26(3): 547–565.Google Scholar
  91. Wilson, R.A., and A. Clark. 2009. How to situate cognition: Letting nature takes its course. In The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition, ed. P. Robbins and M. Aydede, 55–77. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institut für Philosophie IIRuhr Universität BochumCologneGermany

Personalised recommendations