Advertisement

Review of Philosophy and Psychology

, Volume 3, Issue 2, pp 213–230 | Cite as

Theory-Theory and the Direct Perception of Mental States

  • Jane Suilin LavelleEmail author
Article

Abstract

Philosophers and psychologists have often maintained that in order to attribute mental states to other people one must have a ‘theory of mind’. This theory facilitates our grasp of other people’s mental states. Debate has then focussed on the form this theory should take. Recently a new approach has been suggested, which I call the ‘Direct Perception approach to social cognition’. This approach maintains that we can directly perceive other people’s mental states. It opposes traditional views on two counts: by claiming that mental states are observable and by claiming that we can attribute them to others without the need for a theory of mind. This paper argues that there are two readings of the direct perception claims: a strong and a weak one. The Theory-theory is compatible with the weak version but not the strong one. The paper argues that the strong version of direct perception is untenable, drawing on evidence from the mirror neuron literature and arguments from the philosophy of science and perception to support this claim. It suggests that one traditional ‘theory of mind’ view, the ‘Theory-theory’ view, is compatible with the claim that mental states are observable, and concludes that direct perception views do not offer a viable alternative to theory of mind approaches to social cognition.

Keywords

Mental State Perceptual Experience Visual Experience Mirror Neuron Conscious Experience 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Baron-Cohen, S., and Swettenham, J. 1996. The relationship between SAM and ToMM: Two hypotheses. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers, and P. Smith, 158–168. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Botterill, G. 1996. Folk psychology and theoretical status. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers, and P. Smith, 105–119. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Carruthers, P. 2009. How we know our own minds: The relationship between mindreading and metacognition. Behavioural and Brain Sciences 32: 121–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Churchland, P. 1979. Scientific realism and the plasticity of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Csibra, G. 2005, January 2. Mirror neurons and action observation. Is simulation involved? Retrieved from http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/4.
  6. Csibra, G. 2007. Action mirroring and action understanding: An alternative account. In Sensorimotor foundations of higher cognition: Attention and performance XXII, ed. P. Haggard, Y. Rosetti, and M. Kawato, 435–459. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Dretske, F. 1969. Seeing and knowing. London: Routledge & K.Paul.Google Scholar
  8. Fodor, J., and Z. Pylyshyn. 1981. How direct is visual perception? Cognition 9: 139–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Gallagher, S. 2005. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gallagher, S. 2007. Simulation trouble. Social Neuroscience 2: 353–365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gallagher, S. 2008. Direct perception in an intersubjective context. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 535–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gallagher, S., and D. Zahavi. 2008. The phenomenological mind. Oxford: Routledge.Google Scholar
  13. Gallese, V. 2001. The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: From mirror neurons to empathy. Journal of Consciousness Studies 8: 33–50.Google Scholar
  14. Gallese, V. 2006. Embodied simulation: From mirror neuron systems to interpersonal relations. Empathy and fairness, 3–20. Novartis Foundation.Google Scholar
  15. Gallese, V. 2007. Before and below ‘theory of mind’: Embodied simulation and the neural correlates of social cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of the Biological Sciences 362: 659–669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Gallese, V. 2009a. Motor abstraction: A neuroscientific account of how action goals and intentions are mapped and understood. Psychological Research 73: 486–498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Gallese, V. 2009b. We-ness, embodied simulation and psychoanalysis: Reply to commentaries. Psychoanalytic Dialogues 19: 580–584.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Gibson, J. 1979. The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
  19. Goldman, A. 1989. Interpretation psychologized. Mind and Language 4: 161–185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Goldman, A. 2006. Simulating minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Gopnik, A., and A. Meltzoff. 1997. Words, thoughts and theories. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
  22. Gopnik, A., and H. Wellman. 1992. Why the child’s theory of mind really is a theory. Mind and Language 7: 145–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Gordon, R. 1996. ‘Radical’ simulationism. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers and P. Smith, 11–22. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Hanson, N. 1958. Patterns of discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Heal, J. 1996. Simulation, theory and content. In Theories of theories of mind, ed. P. Carruthers and P. Smith, 75–90. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Heyes, C.M. 2001. Causes and consequences of imitation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 5: 245–261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Heyes, C.M. 2005. Imitation by association. In Perspectives on imitation: From mirror neurons to memes, ed. S. Hurley and N. Chater, 157–176. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  28. Heyes, C.M. 2010. Where do mirror neurons come from? Neuroscience and Behavioural Reviews 34: 575–583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Hutto, D. 2008. Folk psychological narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Hutto, D. 2012. Elementary mindreading, enactivist style. In Joint attention: New developments in philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience, ed. A. Seeman, 307–342. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  31. Iacoboni, M., I. Molnar-Szakacs, V. Gallese, G. Buccino, J. Mazziotta, and G. Rizzolatti. 2005. Grasping the intentions of others with one’s own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology 3: 529–535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Jacob, P. 2008. What do mirror neurons contribute to human social cognition? Mind and Language 23: 190–223.Google Scholar
  33. Johnson, S. 2000. The recognition of mentalistic agents in infancy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4:22–28.Google Scholar
  34. Lewis, D. 1970. How to define theoretical terms. The Journal of Philosophy 67: 427–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Morton, A. 2007. Folk psychology does not exist. In Folk psychology re-assessed, ed. D. Hutto and M. Ratcliffe, 211–223. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Premack, D., and G. Woodruff. 1978. Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? The Behavioural and Brain Sciences 1: 515–526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Ratcliffe, M. 2006. ‘Folk psychology’ is not folk psychology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 5: 31–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Reddy, V. 2008. How infants know minds. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Rizzolatti, G., and L. Craighero. 2004. The mirror neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience 27: 169–192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Shapere, D. 1982. The concept of observation in science and philosophy. Philosophy of Science 49: 485–525.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Southgate, V., M. Johnson, T. Osbourne, and G. Csibra. 2009. Predictive motor activation during action observation in human infants. Biology Letters 5: 769–772.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Van Riel, R. 2008. On how we perceive the social world. Consciousness and Cognition 17: 544–552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Wellman, H. 1992. The child’s theory of mind. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of EdinburghEdinburghUK

Personalised recommendations