On Iconic-Discursive Representations: Do they Bring us Closer to a Humean Representational Mind?
- 18 Downloads
Abstract
This paper argues, contrary to Fodor’s well-known position, that the iconic and discursive modes of representation are not mutually exclusive categories. It is argued that there exists at least a third kind of representation which blends the semantic properties of icons and the syntactic properties of discourses. We reason that this iconic-discursive genus behaves differently from other representational formats, such as distributed representations or maps, previously put forward as challenging Fodor’s basic distinction. A reflection follows about how this kind of representation impacts on the Fodorian issues for which the original dual distinction was argumentatively instrumental, namely, the kinds of codes and possible inter-code relations accessible to the representational mind. The suggestion is put forward that iconic-discursive representations may facilitate trade-offs between the world and the representational mind, as well as between the differently complex levels of representation that mediate between percepts and concepts. We conclude that such aspects of the computational mind, which until now appeared to be stubbornly resistant with respect to a conciliation of Hume’s empiricism and Fodor’s computationalism, may be more easily accessed and understood taking advantage of the biosemiotics perspective and acknowledging the richness of the biosemiotics codes accessible to cognition.
Keywords
Representational theory of mind Icons Discourses Likeness CompositionalityNotes
Acknowledgements
This paper has benefitted from a grant of the Spanish Government (Ministerio de Ciencia, Información y Universidades, Ref. FFI2017-87699P). The authors want to express their gratitude to the reviewers for their helpful and insighfiul comments. All remaining errors are our own.
References
- Alexander, V. N., & Grimes, V. (2017). Fluid biosemiotic mechanisms underlie subconscious habits. Biosemiotics, 10, 337–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Atkin, A. (2013). Peirce’s theory of signs. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/peirce-semiotics/.
- Balog, K. (2009). Jerry Fodor and non-conceptual content. Synthese, 170(2), 311–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Barbieri, M. (2009). Three types of semiosis. Biosemiotics, 2, 19–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Barbieri, M. (2013). Organic semiosis and Peircean semiosis. Biosemiotics, 6, 273–289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Beni, M. D. (2017). The code model of biosemiotics and the fate of the structuralist theory of mental representation. Biosemiotics, 10, 99–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bermúdez, J., & Cahen, A. (2015). Nonconceptual mental content. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/content-nonconceptual/.
- Brentano, F. (1874/1973). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
- Bueno, O. (2013). Perception and conception: Shaping human minds. Biosemiotics, 6, 323–336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Campbell, R., MacSweeney, M., & Waters, D. (2007). Sign language and the brain: A review. Journal of Deaf Studies and Deaf Education, 13(1), 3–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Camps, E. (2007). Thinking with maps. Philosophical Perspectives, 21, 145–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Casati, R., & Varzi, A. C. (1999). Parts and places. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Cecilia Tejedor, A. (2004). Mil palabras con las manos… del léxico signado español. Madrid: CEPEGoogle Scholar
- Cerrone, M. (2018). Umwelt and ape language experiments: On the role of iconicity in the human-ape pidgin language. Biosemiotics, 11, 41–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodies cognitive science. Cambridge: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Farias, P., & Queiroz, J. (2006). Images, diagrams, and metaphors: Hypoicons in the context of Peirce’s sixty-six fold classification of signs. Semiotica, 162, 287–307.Google Scholar
- Filippi, P. (2014). Specifically human: Going beyond perceptual syntax. Biosemiotics, 7, 111–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts. Were cognitive science went wrong. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fodor, J. A. (2003). Hume variations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Fodor, J. A. (2007). The revenge of the given. In B. P. McLaughlin & J. Cohn (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 105–116). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Fodor, J. A. (2008). Lot 2. The language of thought revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Fodor, J. A., & Pylyshyn, Z. (2015). Minds without meanings. An essay on the content of concepts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Goldberg, A. (1995). Constructions. A construction grammar approach to argument structure. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Goldin-Meadow, S. (2003). The resilience of language: What gesture creation in deaf children can tell us about how all children learn language. New York: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
- Haugeland, J. (1998). Having thought. Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Hickok, G., Bellugi, U., & Klima, E. S. (1998). The neural organization of language: Evidence from sign language aphasia. Trends in Cognitive Science, 2(4), 129–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hume, D. (1738/2007). In D. F. Norton & M. J. Norton (Eds.), A treatise of human nature (Vol. 1). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Johnson, K. (2015). Maps, languages, and manguages. Rival cognitive architectures? Philosophical Psychology, 28(6), 815–836.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Johnson, M. (1987). The body in the mind. In The bodily basis of meaning, imagination, and reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kosslyn, S. M. (1980). Image and mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Kosslyn, S. M. (2005). Mental images and the brain. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3/4), 333–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kriegeskorte, N., & Kievit, R. A. (2013). Representational geometry: Integrating cognition, computation, and the brain. Trends in Cognitive Science, 17(8), 401–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kulvicki, J. (2003). Image structure. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 61(4), 323–340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kulvicki, J. (2015). Maps, pictures, and predication. Ergo 2. https://doi.org/10.3998/ergo.12405314.0002.007.
- Owen, D. (2009). Hume and the mechanics of mind. Impressions, ideas, and association. In D. F. Norton & J. Taylor (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Hume (pp. 70–104). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Peirce, C. S. (1931). Collected papers. I. Principles of philosophy. II. Elements of logic. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Pitt, D. (2018). Mental representation. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (winter 2018 edition), URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/mental-representation/.
- Poizner, H., Klima, E., & Bellugi, U. (1987). What the hands reveal about the brain. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Seeing and visualizing. It’s not what you think. Cambridge: The MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Rescorla, M. (2009). Predication and cartographic representation. Synthese, 169(1), 175–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sampson, G., & Chen, Z. (2013). The reality of compound ideographs. Journal of Chinese Linguistics, 41(2), 255–272.Google Scholar
- Sellars, W. (1979). Naturalism and ontology. Atascadero: Ridgeview Publishing.Google Scholar
- Senghas, A., Kita, S., & Ozyürek, A. (2007). Children creating core properties of language: Evidence from an emerging sign language in Nicaragua. Science, 305(5691), 1779–1782.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sterelny, K. (1990). The representational theory of mind. An introduction. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Stjernfelt, F. (2015). Dicisings. Peirce’s semiotic doctrine of propositions. Synthese, 192(4), 1019–1054.CrossRefGoogle Scholar