Neuroethics

, Volume 9, Issue 1, pp 1–13

Is Deontology a Moral Confabulation?

Original Paper

Abstract

Joshua Greene has put forward the bold empirical hypothesis that deontology is a confabulation of moral emotions. Deontological philosophy does not steam from "true" moral reasoning, but from emotional reactions, backed up by post hoc rationalizations which play no role in generating the initial moral beliefs. In this paper, I will argue against the confabulation hypothesis. First, I will highlight several points in Greene’s discussion of confabulation, and identify two possible models. Then, I will argue that the evidence does not illustrate the relevant model of deontological confabulation. In fact, I will make the case that deontology is unlikely to be a confabulation because alarm-like emotions, which allegedly drive deontological theorizing, are resistant to be subject to confabulation. I will end by clarifying what kind of claims can the confabulation data support. The upshot of the final section is that confabulation data cannot be used to undermine deontological theory in itself, and ironically, if one commits to the claim that a deontological justification is a confabulation in a particular case, then the data suggests that in general deontology has a prima facie validity.

Keywords

Confabulation Deontology Consequentialism Greene Moral intution 

References

  1. 1.
    Greene J.D. 2014. Beyond point-and-shoot morality: why cognitive (neuro) science matters for ethics. Ethics 124(4): 695–726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Greene, J.D. 2008. The secret joke of Kant’s soul. In Sinnott-Armstrong W. (ed.), Moral Psychology: Vol. 3. The Neuroscience of Morality. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Greene J.D., R.B. Sommerville, L.E. Nystrom, J.M. Darley, and J.D. Cohen. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293(5537): 2105–2108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Greene J.D., L.E. Nystrom, A.D. Engell, J.M. Darley, and J.D. Cohen. 2004. The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44(2): 389–400.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Kahane G., and N. Shackel. 2010. Methodological issues in the neuroscience of moral judgement. Mind & Language 25(5): 561–582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Mihailov E. 2015. The argument from self-defeating beliefs against deontology. Ethical Perspectives 22(4): 573–600.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Kahane G. 2012. On the wrong track: process and content in moral psychology. Mind & Language 27(5): 519–545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Greene J.D., F.A. Cushman, L.E. Stewart, K. Lowenberg, L.E. Nystrom, and J.D. Cohen. 2009. Pushing moral buttons: the interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition 111(3): 364–371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Cushman F., L. Young, and J.D. Greene. 2010. Our multi-system moral psychology: towards a consensus view. In The moral psychology handbook, 47–71. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Berker S. 2009. The normative insignificance of neuroscience. Philosophy & Public Affairs 37(4): 293–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Kamm F.M. 1998. Moral intuitions, cognitive psychology, and the harming-versus-not-aiding distinction. Ethics 463-488.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Wilson T.D. 2009. Strangers to ourselves: discovering the adaptive unconscious. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Dean R. 2010. Does neuroscience undermine deontological Theory?. Neuroethics 3(1): 43–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Wielenberg E.J. 2014. Robust ethics: The metaphysics and epistemology of godless normative realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. 15.
    Kamm F.M. 2009. Neuroscience and moral reasoning: a note on recent research. Philosophy & Public Affairs 37(4): 330–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Greene J.D. 2014. Moral tribes: emotion, reason and the gap between us and them. London: Atlantic Books.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
    Hirstein W. 2009. Introduction: what is confabulation?. In Confabulation: views from neuroscience, psychiatry, psychology and philosophy, ed. W. Hirstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    Greene J.D., S.A. Morelli, K. Lowenberg, L.E. Nystrom, and J.D. Cohen. 2008. Cognitive load selectively interferes with utilitarian moral judgment. Cognition 107(3): 1144–1154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Hume David. 1739. A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Haidt J., F. Bjorklund, and S. Murphy. 2000. Moral dumbfounding: when intuition finds no reason. University of Virginia: Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
  21. 21.
    Nisbett R.E., and T.D. Wilson. 1977. Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychological Review 84(3): 231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Maier N.R. 1931. Reasoning in humans. II. The solution of a problem and its appearance in consciousness. Journal of Comparative Psychology 12(2): 181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    Dutton D.G., and A.P. Aron. 1974. Some evidence for heightened sexual attraction under conditions of high anxiety. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 30(4): 510.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Stuss D.T., M.P. Alexander, A. Lieberman, and H. Levine. 1978. An extraordinary form of confabulation. Neurology 28(11): 1166–1166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. 25.
    Estabrooks G.H. 1943. Hypnotism. New York: Dutton.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    Gazzaniga M.S., and J.E. LeDoux. 1978. The integrated mind. New York: Plenum Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. 27.
    Thomson J.J. 1986. Rights, restitution, and risk: essays in moral theory. Harvard: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Kamm F.M. 1993. Morality and mortality, vol 1. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    McGinn C. 1999. Our duties to animals and the poor. In Singer and his critics, ed. Dale Jamieson. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
  30. 30.
    Kamm F.M. 1999. Famine ethics: the problem of distance in morality and singer's ethical theory. In Singer and his critics, ed. Dale Jamieson. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.Google Scholar
  31. 31.
    Kant I. 1999. Practical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  32. 32.
    Haidt J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 108(4): 814.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. 33.
    Kelly D.R. 2011. Yuck!: The nature and moral significance of disgust. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  34. 34.
    Newell B.R., and D.R. Shanks. 2014. Unconscious influences on decision making: a critical review. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37(01): 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. 35.
    Oakley D.A., and P.W. Halligan. 2013. Hypnotic suggestion: opportunities for cognitive neuroscience. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 14(8): 565–576.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 36.
    Hirstein W. 2005. Brain fiction: self-deception and the riddle of confabulation. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  37. 37.
    Schnider A. 2008. The confabulating mind: How the brain creates reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. 38.
    Wheatley T. 2009. Everyday confabulation. In Confabulation: views from neuroscience, psychiatry, psychology and philosophy, ed. W. Hirstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  39. 39.
    Burgess P.W., and T. Shallice. 1996. Confabulation and the control of recollection. Memory 4(4): 359–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. 40.
    Mercer B., W. Wapner, H. Gardner, and D.F. Benson. 1977. A study of confabulation. Archives of Neurology 34(7): 429–433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. 41.
    Roediger H.L., J.M. Watson, K.B. McDermott, and D.A. Gallo. 2001. Factors that determine false recall: a multiple regression analysis. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 8(3): 385–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. 42.
    Wilson T.D., and R.E. Nisbett. 1978. The accuracy of verbal reports about the effects of stimuli on evaluations and behavior. Social Psychology 41: 118–131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. 43.
    Cushman F., L. Young, and M. Hauser. 2006. The role of conscious reasoning and intuition in moral judgment testing three principles of harm. Psychological Science 17(12): 1082–1089.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. 44.
    Slovic P., and S. Lichtenstein. 1971. Comparison of Bayesian and regression approaches to the study of information processing in judgment. Organizational Behaviour and Human Performance 6: 649–744.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. 45.
    O’Neill O. 2005. The dark side of human rights. International Affairs 81(2): 427–439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 46.
    Tversky A., and D. Kahneman. 1974. Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science 185(4157): 1124–1131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. 47.
    Kahneman D. 2011. Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Romanian AcademyIasiRomania
  2. 2.Research Center in Applied Ethics, Faculty of PhilosophyUniversity of BucharestBucharestRomania

Personalised recommendations