Abstract
Corroborative evidence may be understood as having two epistemic effects: a primary effect by which it offers direct evidence for some claim, and a secondary effect by which it bolsters the appraised probative, or evidential, value of some other piece of evidence for that claim. This paper argues that the bolstering effect of corroborative evidence is epistemically legitimate because corroboration provides a reason to count the belief based on the initial evidence as sensitive to, and safe from, defeat in a way that it was not previously recognized to be. Discovering that our initial evidence tracks the truth in a way we previously did not recognize provides a reason to positively reappraise the probative value of that evidence. The final section of the paper relates the proposed sensitivity- and safety-based account of corroboration to an explanation-based account.
Keywords
Corroboration Corroborative evidence Inference to the best explanation Safety Sensitivity Truth trackingNotes
Acknowledgements
Earlier versions of this paper were presented as conference presentations at the Canadian Society for Epistemology, Université de Sherbrooke, Québec, on 23 November 2012, and the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology 105th Annual Meeting, Austin, Texas, on 28 February 2013, and as philosophy department talks at Old Dominion University, on 5 February 2013, the University of Waterloo, on 7 April 2016, McMaster University, on 8 April 2016, and the University of Nevada, Las Vegas, on 7 October 2016. Of those audiences, thanks are especially due to Dale Miller, David Matheson, Cecilea Mun, and Bill Roche for their insightful and instructive comments. Thanks to David Matheson for, early on in this project, calling my attention to the fact that, in addition to making a view defeasibly sensitive, corroboration similarly makes it defeasibly safe. To Scott Aikin, Keith DeRose, Catherine Elgin, John Grey, Matt McKeon, and Duncan Pritchard I offer my sincere thanks for their careful readings of earlier versions of this paper, for their illuminating and constructive criticisms, and for their encouragement of the project generally. Additionally, the anonymous reviewers of this paper have my thanks.
References
- Alspector-Kelly, M. (2011). Why safety doesn’t save closure. Synthese, 183, 127–142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Baumann, P. (2012). Nozick’s defense of closure. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 81–97). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.Google Scholar
- Becker, K. (2012). Methods and how to individuate them. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 1–8). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Black, T., & Murphy, P. (2007). In defense of sensitivity. Synthese, 154, 53–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Carnap, R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Coady, C. A. (1992). Testimony: a philosophical study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Cohen, L. J. (1977). The probable and the provable. Oxford: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Comesaña, J. (2005). Unsafe knowledge. Synthese, 146, 393–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cross, T. (2010). Skeptical success. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 3, pp. 35–62). Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
- DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review, 104, 1–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- DeRose, K. (2004). Sosa, safety, sensitivity, and skeptical problems. In J. Greco (Ed.), Ernest Sosa and his critics (pp. 22–41). Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- DeRose, K. (2010). Insensitivity is back, baby! Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 161–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Elgin, C. (2014). Non-foundationalist epistemology: holism, coherence and tenability. In M. Steup, J. Turri, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (2nd ed., pp. 244–255). Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Forbes, G. (1984). Nozick on scepticism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 43–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Godden, D. (2010). Corroborative evidence. In C. Reed & C.W. Tindale (Eds.), Dialectics, dialogue and argumentation: An examination of Douglas Walton's theories of reasoning and argument (pp. 201-212). London: College Publications.Google Scholar
- Godden, D. (2014). Modeling corroborative evidence: Inference to the best explanation as counter-rebuttal. Argumentation, 28, 187-220.Google Scholar
- Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Greco, J. (2012). Better safe than sensitive. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 193–206). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
- Hawthorne, J. (2005). The case for closure. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (1st ed., pp. 26–41). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Kvanvig, J. (2004). Nozickian epistemology and the value of knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 14, 201–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kvanvig, J. (2012). Truth-tracking and the value of knowledge. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 101–121). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lipton, P. (1990). Contrastive explanation. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 27, 247–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Luper, S. (2012). False negatives. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 207–226). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Luper-Foy. S. [now “Luper”]. (1984). The epistemic predicament: knowledge, Nozickian tracking, and scepticism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89, 47–58.Google Scholar
- Murphy, P. (2005). Closure failures for safety. Philosophia, 33, 331–334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Murphy, P., & Black, T. (2012). Sensitivity meets explanation: an improved counterfactual condition on knowledge. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 28–42). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Neta, R., & Rohrbaugh, G. (2004). Luminosity and the safety of knowledge. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 85, 396–406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
- Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Pritchard, D. (2008). Sensitivity, safety, and antiluck epistemology. In J. Greco (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of scepticism (pp. 437–455). Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
- Pritchard, D. (2012). In defence of modest anti-luck epistemology. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 173–192). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Redmayne, M. (2000). A corroboration approach to recovered memories of sexual abuse: a note of caution. Law Quarterly Review, 116, 147–155.Google Scholar
- Roush, S. (2005). Tracking truth: Knowledge, evidence, and science. Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
- Russell, B. (1948 1992). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Sosa, E. (1999). How to defeat opposition to Moore. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 141–154.Google Scholar
- Sosa, E. (2002). Tracking, competence, and knowledge. In P. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 264–286). Oxford: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Vogel, J. (1987). Tracking, closure, and inductive knowledge. In S. Luper-Foy (Ed.), The possibility of knowledge: Nozick and his critics (pp. 197–215). Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Vogel, J. (2012). The enduring trouble with tracking. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 122–151). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
- Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 65–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar