Advertisement

Acta Analytica

, Volume 34, Issue 1, pp 15–38 | Cite as

Corroboration: Sensitivity, Safety, and Explanation

  • David GoddenEmail author
Article
  • 30 Downloads

Abstract

Corroborative evidence may be understood as having two epistemic effects: a primary effect by which it offers direct evidence for some claim, and a secondary effect by which it bolsters the appraised probative, or evidential, value of some other piece of evidence for that claim. This paper argues that the bolstering effect of corroborative evidence is epistemically legitimate because corroboration provides a reason to count the belief based on the initial evidence as sensitive to, and safe from, defeat in a way that it was not previously recognized to be. Discovering that our initial evidence tracks the truth in a way we previously did not recognize provides a reason to positively reappraise the probative value of that evidence. The final section of the paper relates the proposed sensitivity- and safety-based account of corroboration to an explanation-based account.

Keywords

Corroboration Corroborative evidence Inference to the best explanation Safety Sensitivity Truth tracking 

Notes

Acknowledgements

Earlier versions of this paper were presented as conference presentations at the Canadian Society for Epistemology, Université de Sherbrooke, Québec, on 23 November 2012, and the Southern Society for Philosophy and Psychology 105th Annual Meeting, Austin, Texas, on 28 February 2013, and as philosophy department talks at Old Dominion University, on 5 February 2013, the University of Waterloo, on 7 April 2016, McMaster University, on 8 April 2016, and the University of Nevada, Las Vegas, on 7 October 2016. Of those audiences, thanks are especially due to Dale Miller, David Matheson, Cecilea Mun, and Bill Roche for their insightful and instructive comments. Thanks to David Matheson for, early on in this project, calling my attention to the fact that, in addition to making a view defeasibly sensitive, corroboration similarly makes it defeasibly safe. To Scott Aikin, Keith DeRose, Catherine Elgin, John Grey, Matt McKeon, and Duncan Pritchard I offer my sincere thanks for their careful readings of earlier versions of this paper, for their illuminating and constructive criticisms, and for their encouragement of the project generally. Additionally, the anonymous reviewers of this paper have my thanks.

References

  1. Alspector-Kelly, M. (2011). Why safety doesn’t save closure. Synthese, 183, 127–142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Baumann, P. (2012). Nozick’s defense of closure. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 81–97). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.Google Scholar
  3. Becker, K. (2012). Methods and how to individuate them. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 1–8). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Black, T., & Murphy, P. (2007). In defense of sensitivity. Synthese, 154, 53–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. (1962). Logical foundations of probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  6. Coady, C. A. (1992). Testimony: a philosophical study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Cohen, L. J. (1977). The probable and the provable. Oxford: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Comesaña, J. (2005). Unsafe knowledge. Synthese, 146, 393–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cross, T. (2010). Skeptical success. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 3, pp. 35–62). Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
  10. DeRose, K. (1995). Solving the skeptical problem. Philosophical Review, 104, 1–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. DeRose, K. (2004). Sosa, safety, sensitivity, and skeptical problems. In J. Greco (Ed.), Ernest Sosa and his critics (pp. 22–41). Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. DeRose, K. (2010). Insensitivity is back, baby! Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 161–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Elgin, C. (2014). Non-foundationalist epistemology: holism, coherence and tenability. In M. Steup, J. Turri, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (2nd ed., pp. 244–255). Oxford: Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
  14. Forbes, G. (1984). Nozick on scepticism. The Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 43–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Godden, D. (2010). Corroborative evidence. In C. Reed & C.W. Tindale (Eds.), Dialectics, dialogue and argumentation: An examination of Douglas Walton's theories of reasoning and argument (pp. 201-212). London: College Publications.Google Scholar
  17. Godden, D. (2014). Modeling corroborative evidence: Inference to the best explanation as counter-rebuttal. Argumentation, 28, 187-220.Google Scholar
  18. Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Greco, J. (2012). Better safe than sensitive. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 193–206). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
  21. Hawthorne, J. (2005). The case for closure. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (1st ed., pp. 26–41). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  22. Kvanvig, J. (2004). Nozickian epistemology and the value of knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 14, 201–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kvanvig, J. (2012). Truth-tracking and the value of knowledge. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 101–121). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Lipton, P. (1990). Contrastive explanation. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 27, 247–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Luper, S. (2012). False negatives. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 207–226). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Luper-Foy. S. [now “Luper”]. (1984). The epistemic predicament: knowledge, Nozickian tracking, and scepticism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89, 47–58.Google Scholar
  27. Murphy, P. (2005). Closure failures for safety. Philosophia, 33, 331–334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Murphy, P., & Black, T. (2012). Sensitivity meets explanation: an improved counterfactual condition on knowledge. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 28–42). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Neta, R., & Rohrbaugh, G. (2004). Luminosity and the safety of knowledge. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 85, 396–406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard UP.Google Scholar
  31. Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Pritchard, D. (2008). Sensitivity, safety, and antiluck epistemology. In J. Greco (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of scepticism (pp. 437–455). Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
  33. Pritchard, D. (2012). In defence of modest anti-luck epistemology. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 173–192). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Redmayne, M. (2000). A corroboration approach to recovered memories of sexual abuse: a note of caution. Law Quarterly Review, 116, 147–155.Google Scholar
  35. Roush, S. (2005). Tracking truth: Knowledge, evidence, and science. Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
  36. Russell, B. (1948 1992). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  37. Sosa, E. (1999). How to defeat opposition to Moore. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 141–154.Google Scholar
  38. Sosa, E. (2002). Tracking, competence, and knowledge. In P. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 264–286). Oxford: Oxford UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Vogel, J. (1987). Tracking, closure, and inductive knowledge. In S. Luper-Foy (Ed.), The possibility of knowledge: Nozick and his critics (pp. 197–215). Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  40. Vogel, J. (2012). The enduring trouble with tracking. In K. Becker & T. Black (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 122–151). Cambridge: Cambridge UP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford UP.Google Scholar
  42. Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. The Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 65–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyMichigan State UniversityEast LansingUSA

Personalised recommendations