Acta Analytica

, Volume 29, Issue 4, pp 457–468 | Cite as

The Problem of Massive Deception for Justification Norms of Action

Article

Abstract

In this paper, I argue against recent versions of justification norms of action and practical deliberation (Neta, Noûs 43:684–699, 2009; Gerken, Synthese 178:529–547, 2011, Synthese 189:373–394, 2012; Smithies, Noûs 46:265–288, 2012). I demonstrate that these norms yield unacceptable results in deception cases. However, a further modification of justification norms in the light of these results appears to be ad hoc. Hence, I claim, we should reject justification norms of action and practical deliberation.

Keywords

Knowledge Justification Action Practical deliberation Norms 

References

  1. Arpaly, N., & Schroeder, T. (2012). Deliberation and acting for reasons. Philosophical Review, 121(2), 209–239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bach, K. (1985). A rationale for reliabilism. The Monist, 68(2), 246–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Brown, J. (2008). Knowledge and practical reason. Philosophy Compass, 3(6), 1135–1152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Brown, J. (2012). Assertion and practical reasoning: common or divergent epistemic standards? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(1), 123–157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Burge, T. (2003). Perceptual entitlement. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(3), 503–548.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Cohen, S. (1984). Justification and truth. Philosophical Studies, 46(3), 279–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Comesaña, J. (2002). The diagonal and the demon. Philosophical Studies, 110(3), 249–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Comesaña, J. (2005). We are (almost) all externalists now. Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 59–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Engel, M. (1992). Personal and doxastic justification in epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 67(2), 133–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gerken, M. (2011). Warrant and action. Synthese, 178(3), 529–547.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gerken, M. (2012). Discursive justification and skepticism. Synthese, 189(2), 373–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gerken, M. (2013). The roles of knowledge ascriptions in epistemic assessment. European Journal of Philosophy.http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/ejop.12026.
  13. Gerken, M. (2014). Same, same but different: the epistemic norms of assertion, action and practical reasoning. Philosophical Studies, 168(3), 725–744.Google Scholar
  14. Gibbons, J. (2010). Things that make things reasonable. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(2), 335–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Graham, P. J. (2012). Epistemic entitlement. Noûs, 46(3), 449–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hawthorne, J. (2004). Knowledge and lotteries. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Hawthorne, J., & Stanley, J. (2008). Knowledge and action. Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 571–590.Google Scholar
  19. Hyman, J. (1999). How knowledge works. Philosophical Quarterly, 50(197), 433–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Ichikawa, J. J. (2012). Knowledge norms and acting well. Thought, 1(1), 49–55.Google Scholar
  21. Lehrer, K., & Cohen, S. (1983). Justification, truth, and coherence. Synthese, 55(2), 191–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Littlejohn, C. (2009a). Must we act only on what we know? Journal of Philosophy, 106(8), 463–473.Google Scholar
  23. Littlejohn, C. (2009b). On treating something as a reason for action. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy.Google Scholar
  24. Littlejohn, C. (2012). Justification and the truth-connection. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. McKenna, R. (2013). Why Assertion and practical reasoning are possibly not governed by the same epistemic norm. Logos and Episteme.Google Scholar
  26. McKinnon, R. (2012). What I learned in the lunch room about assertion and practical reasoning. Logos and Episteme, 3(4), 565–569.Google Scholar
  27. Montminy, M. (2013). Why assertion and practical reasoning must be governed by the same epistemic norm. Logos and Episteime, 4(4), 457–464.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Neta, R. (2009). Treating something as a reason for action. Noûs, 43(4), 684–699.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Smith, M. (2012). Some thoughts on the JK-rule. Noûs, 46(4), 791–802.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Smithies, D. (2012). The normative role of knowledge. Noûs, 46(2), 265–288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Smithies, D. (2014). Why justification matters. In D. Henderson, & J. Greco (Eds.), Epistemic evaluation: point and purpose in epistemology. Oxford University Press, in press.Google Scholar
  32. Stanley, J. (2005). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Sutton, J. (2007). Without justification. Mit Press.Google Scholar
  34. Henderson, D., Horgan T., Potrč, M. (2007). Transglobal evidentialism-reliabilism, Acta Analytica, 22(4), 281–300.Google Scholar
  35. Unger, P. K. (1975). Ignorance: a case for scepticism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Weatherson, B. (2008). Deontology and descartes’s demon. Journal of Philosophy, 105(9), 540–569.Google Scholar
  37. Wedgwood, R. (2002). Internalism explained. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(2), 349–369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Département de philosophieUniversité de GenèveGenèveSwitzerland

Personalised recommendations