Acta Analytica

, Volume 27, Issue 4, pp 461–478 | Cite as

Factive Presupposition and the Truth Condition on Knowledge

Article

Abstract

In this paper I argue, against some recent criticisms, that the factivity of “knows” does not support the traditional truth condition on knowledge. I articulate a conception of the factivity of “knows” on which it is a matter of cancelable pragmatic presupposition, and consider the epistemological implications of this.

Keywords

Knowledge Presupposition Factive verbs 

References

  1. Abbott, B. (2006). Where have some of the presuppositions gone? In B. Birner and G. Ward (Eds.), Drawing the boundaries of meaning: Neo-Gricean studies in pragmatics and semantics in honor of Laurence R. Horn (pp. 1–30). John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  2. Abusch, D. (2002). Lexical alternatives as a source of pragmatic presuppositions. In B. Jackson (Ed.), Proceedings of SALT XII (pp. 1–20). CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  3. Atlas, J. D. (2004). Presupposition. In L.R. Horn and G. Ward (Eds.), The handbook of pragmatics (pp. 29–52). Blackwell.Google Scholar
  4. BonJour, L. (2002). Epistemology: Classic problems and contemporary responses. Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  5. Buckwalter, W. (ms), Factive verbs and protagonist projection.Google Scholar
  6. Cohen, L. J. (1992). An essay on belief and acceptance. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Feldman, R. (2003). Epistemology. Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  9. Frege, G. (1892). On Sense and Reference. In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (1970) (pp. 56–78). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Frege, G. (1919). Negation. In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (1970) (pp. 117–35). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Fumerton, R. (2006). Epistemology. Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Glanzberg, M. (2005). Presupposition, truth values, and expressing propositions. In G. Preyer and G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, truth, and meaning (pp. 349–96). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Goldman, A. (2002). Pathways to knowledge: Private and public. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Grice, H. P. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Hannon, M. (forthcoming). ‘Knows’ entails truth. Journal of Philosophical Research. Google Scholar
  17. Hazlett, A. (2009). Knowledge and conversation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78(3), 591–620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hazlett, A. (2010). The myth of factive verbs. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 80(3), 497–522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Holton, R. (1997). Some telling examples: a reply to Tsohatzidis. Journal of Pragmatics, 28, 625–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Holton, R. (ms). Facts, factives, and contra-factives.Google Scholar
  21. Karttunen, L. (1971). Some observations on factivity. Papers in Linguistics, 5, 55–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Karttunen, L., & Peters, L. (1979). Conventional implicature. In C. Oh and D. A. Dinneen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, Volume 11: Presupposition (pp. 1–56). Academic Press.Google Scholar
  23. Katz, J. (1979). A solution to the projection problem for presupposition. In C. Oh and D. A. Dinneen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, Volume 11: Presupposition (pp. 91–126). Academic Press.Google Scholar
  24. Kiparsky, P., & Kiparsky, C. (1971). Fact. In D. D. Steinberg and L. A. Jakobovits (Eds.), Semantics: An interdisciplinary reader in philosophy, linguistics, and psychology (pp. 345–69). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Kusch, M. (2009). Testimony and the value of knowledge. In A. Haddock, A. Milar, and D. Pitchard (Eds.), Epistemic value (pp. 60–94). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Moore, G. E. (1993). Moore’s Paradox. In T. Baldwin (Ed.), Selected Writings (pp. 207–212). Routledge.Google Scholar
  27. Simons, M. (2001). On the conversational basis of some presuppositions. In R. Hastings, B. Jackson, and Z. Zvolensky (Eds.), Proceedings of semantics and linguistics theory 11 (pp. 431–48). CLC Publications.Google Scholar
  28. Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge, Volume 1. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Stalnaker, R. (1999). Pragmatic presuppositions. In his Context and content (pp. 45–62). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Strawson, P. F. (1950). On referring. Mind, 59, 230–44.Google Scholar
  31. Strawson, P. F. (1952). Introduction to logical theory. Methuen.Google Scholar
  32. Tsohatzidis, S. (2012). How to forget that “know” is factive. Acta Analytica. doi:10.1007/s12136-012-0150-8.
  33. Turri, J. (2011). Mythology of the factive. Logos & Episteme, 2(1), 143–52.Google Scholar
  34. van Fraasen, B. C. (1971). Formal semantics and logic. Macmillan.Google Scholar
  35. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Weiner, M. (2006). Are all conversational implicatures cancellable? Analysis, 66(2), 127–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of EdinburghEdinburghScotland

Personalised recommendations