Advertisement

Acta Analytica

, Volume 27, Issue 2, pp 199–216 | Cite as

What’s so Good about a Wise and Knowledgeable Public?

  • Kristoffer Ahlstrom-VijEmail author
Article
  • 232 Downloads

Abstract

Philosophers have been concerned for some time with the epistemic caliber of the general public, qua the body that is, ultimately, tasked with political decision-making in democratic societies. Unfortunately, the empirical data paint a pretty dismal picture here, indicating that the public tends to be largely ignorant on the issues relevant to governance. To make matters worse, empirical research on how ignorance tends to breed overconfidence suggests that the public will not only lack knowledge on the relevant issues, but also wisdom, in the Socratic sense of an awareness of your ignorance. While increasing the knowledge and wisdom of the public might be thought an obvious remedy, there is, as far as sound political decision-making and action are concerned, nothing particularly valuable about knowledge or wisdom per se. In fact, it might just be that what the public needs is nothing but the most basic epistemic good: true belief.

Keywords

Knowledge Wisdom Overconfidence Public ignorance 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I want to thank the participants at the 2011 Bled Epistemology Conference, Lingnan University’s philosophy seminar, and the SERG Research Seminar at the University of Copenhagen for valuable discussion. I’m particularly grateful to Derek Baker, Anne Baril, Mikkel Gerken, David Henderson, Mikael Janvid, Klemens Kappel, Chris Kelp, Paisley Livingston, Nikolaj Jang Lee Linding Pedersen, Jim Rice, Wayne Riggs, Kelly Trogdon, and Sarah Wright. Research underlying the present paper was conducted with generous support from the Velux Foundation.

References

  1. Ahlstrom-Vij, K. (forthcoming). Why Deliberative Democracy is (Still) Untenable. Public Affairs Quarterly.Google Scholar
  2. Asch, S. (1955). Opinions and Social Pressure. Scientific American, 193(5), 31–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bartels, L. (1996). Uninformed Voters: Information Effects in Presidential Elections. American Journal of Political Science, 40(1), 194–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Benhabib, S. (1996). Toward a Deliberative Model of Democratic Legitimacy. In S. Benhabib (Ed.), Democracy and Difference (pp. 67–94). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bishop, M., & Trout, J. D. (2005). Epistemology and the Psychology of Human Judgment. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Broadie, S., & Rowe, C. (2002). Aristotle: Nichomachean Ethics. Translated by C. Rowe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Carpini, M. D., & Keeter, S. (1996). What Americans Know about Politics and Why It Matters. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Conee, E. (1998). Seeing the Truth. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58, 847–857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cooper, J. M. (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  10. Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., & Murdoch, D. (1985). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes (Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Darwin, C. (1871). The Descent of Man. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
  12. Dunning, D., Johnson, K., Ehrlinger, J., & Kruger, J. (2003). Why People Fail to Recognize Their Own Incompetence. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 12(3), 83–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Ehrlinger, J., Johnson, K., Banner, M., Dunning, D., & Kruger, J. (2008). Why the Unskilled are Unaware: Further Explorations of (Absent) Self-Insight Among the Incompetent. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 105, 98–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gigone, D., & Hastie, R. (1993). The Common Knowledge Effect: Information Sharing and Group Judgment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 65(5), 959–974.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (Eds.). (2002). Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Goldman, A. (2001). Experts: Which Ones Should You Trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64(1), 85–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Goldman, A., & Olsson, E. J. (2009). Reliabilism and the Value of Knowledge. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic Value (pp. 19–41). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Greco, J. (2007). The Nature of Ability and the Purpose of Knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 17, 57–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Greco, J. (2009). Knowledge and Success from Ability. Philosophical Studies, 142, 17–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Haddock, A., Millar, A., & Pritchard, D. (Eds.). (2009). Epistemic Value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Hastie, R. (1986). Experimental Evidence on Group Accuracy. In B. Grofman & G. Owen (Eds.), Decision Research (Vol. 2, pp. 129–157). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press.Google Scholar
  22. King, C. S. (2008). Wisdom, Moderation, and the Elenchus in Plato’s Apology. Metaphilosophy, 39(3), 345–362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kruger, J., & Dunning, D. (1999). Unskilled and Unaware of It: How Difficulties in Recognizing One’s Own Incompetence Lead to Inflated Self-Assessments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(6), 1121–1134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Kvanvig, J. (2003). The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kvanvig, J. (2009). Responses to Critics. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic Value (pp. 339–352). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Lackey, J. (2007). Why We Don’t Deserve Credit for Everything We Know. Synthese, 158(3), 345–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Lackey, J. (2009). Knowledge and Credit. Philosophical Studies, 142(1), 27–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Laughlin, P. R., Bonner, B. L., & Miner, A. G. (2002). Groups Perform Better Than the Best Individuals on Letters-to-Numbers Problems. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 88, 605–620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Moshman, D., & Geil, M. (1998). Collaborative Reasoning: Evidence for Collective Rationality. Thinking and Reasoning, 4(3), 231–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Nozick, R. (1989). What is Wisdom and Why do Philosophers Love it So? In The Examined Life: Philosophical Medications. New York: Touchstone Press, pp. 267-278.Google Scholar
  31. Olsson, E. J. (2007). Reliabilism, Stability, and the Value of Knowledge. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(4), 343–355.Google Scholar
  32. Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic Luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Pritchard, D. (2007). Recent Work on Epistemic Value. American Philosophical Quarterly, 44(2), 58–110.Google Scholar
  34. Pronin, E., Lin, D. Y., & Ross, L. (2002). The Bias Blind Spot: Perceptions of Bias in Self versus Others. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 28, 369–381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Riggs, W. (2002). Reliability and the Value of Knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64, 79–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Riggs, W. (2007). “Why Epistemologists Are So Down On Their Luck. Synthese, 158, 329–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Ryan, S. (1999). What is Wisdom? Philosophical Studies, 93, 119–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Ryan, S. (2007), Wisdom. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wisdom
  39. Sartwell, C. (1992). Why Knowledge is Merely True Belief. Journal of Philosophy, 89, 167–180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Sieck, W., & Arkes, H. (2005). The Recalcitrance of Overconfidence and its Contribution to Decision Aid Neglect. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 18, 29–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Stasson, M. F., Kameda, T., Parks, C. D., Zimmerman, S. K., & Davis, J. H. (1991). Effects of Assigned Group Consensus Requirement on Group Problem Solving and Group Members’ Learning. Social Psychology Quarterly, 54, 25–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Sternberg, R., & Jordan, J. (Eds.). (2005). A Handbook of Wisdom: Psychological Perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Sunstein, C. R. (2006). Infotopia: How Many Minds Produce Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Talisse, R. (2005). Deliberative Democracy Defended: A Response to Posner’s Political Realism. Res Publica, 11, 185–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Taylor, S. E. (1989). Positive Illusions: Creative Self-Deception and the Healthy Mind. Basic Books.Google Scholar
  46. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and Its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Young, I. (2000). Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of CopenhagenCopenhagenDenmark

Personalised recommendations