Acta Analytica

, Volume 25, Issue 3, pp 285–298

A Deflationary Metaphysics of Morality

Article
  • 88 Downloads

Abstract

The metaphysical dispute between moral realists and antirealists is cast in terms of properties: the realist holds that moral properties exist, the antirealist denies this claim. There is a longstanding philosophical dispute over the nature of properties, and the obscurity of properties may make the realist/antirealist dispute even more obscure. In the spirit of deflationary theories of truth, we can turn to a deflationary theory of properties in order to clarify this issue. One might reasonably worry that such an account of properties would not be capable of properly characterizing disputes regarding the existence or nonexistence of genuine moral properties. In this paper, I will show that, within this framework, the traditional disputes over the existence of moral properties can be characterized in a far clearer fashion than is usually the case. A deflationary account of properties, along with an explanatory hierarchy of properties, makes the dispute in ontology clear.

Keywords

Ontology Metaethics Properties Deflationism Realism 

References

  1. Blackburn, S. (1988). How to be an ethical anti-realist. In S. Darwall, A. Gibbard & P. Railton (Eds.), Moral discourse and practice: Some philosophical approaches (1997) (pp. 167–178). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Blackburn, S. (1999). Is objectively moral justification possible on a quasi-realist foundation? Inquiry, 42(2), 213–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Chrisman, M. (2008). Expressivism, inferentialism, and saving the debate. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77(2), 334–358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Dreier, J. (2004). Meta-ethics and the problem of creeping minimalism. Philosophical Perspectives, 18(1), 23–44.Google Scholar
  5. Dreier, J. (2006). “Was Moore a Moorean?”. In T. Horgan & M. Timmons (Eds.), Metaethics after Moore (pp. 191–208). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  6. Fine, K. (2001). The question of realism. Philosopher's Imprint, I(2), 1–30.Google Scholar
  7. Gibbard, A. (2003). Thinking how to live. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for philosophers: Unweaving the Rainbow. Cambridge, Mass.: Hackett.Google Scholar
  9. Harman, G. (1977). The nature of morality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Horwich, P. (1993). Gibbard's theory of norms. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 22(1), 67–78.Google Scholar
  11. Horwich, P. (1998). Truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Moore, G. E. (1903). Principia ethica. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Moore, G. E. (1968). A reply to my critics. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of G. E. Moore (1968) (pp. 533–677). La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
  14. O'Leary-Hawthorne, J., & Price, H. (1996). How to stand up for non-cognitivists. The Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(2), 275–292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Shafer-Landau, R. (2006). Ethics as philosophy: A defense of ethical nonnaturalism. In R. Shafer-Landau & T. Cuneo (Eds.), Foundations of ethics (2007) (pp. 210–221). Malden, Ma.: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  17. Sturgeon, N. (1985). Moral explanations. In R. Shafer-Landau & T. Cuneo (Eds.), Foundations of ethics (2007) (pp. 337–352). Melden, Ma.: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  18. Sturgeon, N. (2006). Moral explanations defended. In J. Dreier (Ed.), Contemporary debates in moral theory (pp. 241–262). Melden, Ma.: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Oakland UniversityPhilosophyRochesterUSA

Personalised recommendations