Metaphysica

, Volume 14, Issue 1, pp 93–107

In Defence of Powerful Qualities

Article

Abstract

The ontology of ‘powerful qualities’ is gaining an increasing amount of attention in the literature on properties. This is the view that the so-called categorical or qualitative properties are identical with ‘dispositional’ properties. The position is associated with C.B. Martin, John Heil, Galen Strawson and Jonathan Jacobs. Robert Schroer (2012) has recently mounted a number of criticisms against the powerful qualities view as conceived by these main adherents, and has also advanced his own (radically different) version of the view. In this paper I have three main aims: firstly, I shall defend the ontology from his critique, arguing that his criticisms do not damage the position. Secondly, I shall argue that Schroer’s own version of the view is untenable. Thirdly, the paper shall serve to clear up some conceptual confusions that often bedevil the powerful qualities view.

Keywords

Powerful qualities Categorical properties Dispositional properties Partial consideration Phenomenal consciousness 

References

  1. Armstrong, D. M. (1997) A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Armstrong, D. M. (2005) Four Disputes About Properties. Synthese. 144: 309–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Armstrong, D. M., Martin, C.B. and Place, U.T. (1996) Dispositions: A Debate. Crane, T. (ed.) Cornwall, Routledge.Google Scholar
  4. Balog, K. (2008) Phenomenal Concepts. In: Mclaughlin, B., Beckermann, A. and Walter, S. (eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. New York, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bird, A. (2007) Natures Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. New York, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Chalmers, D. J. (1996) The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. USA, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Chalmers, D. J. (2010) The Character of Consciousness. New York, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Ehring, D. (2011) Tropes: properties, objects and mental causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Ellis, B. and Lierse, C. (1994) Dispositional Essentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 72: 27–45.Google Scholar
  10. Gibb, S. C. (2012) Trope Simplicity. In: Garcia, R. (ed.) Substance: New Essays. Philosophia Verlag.Google Scholar
  11. Goff, P. (2011) A-posteriori Physicalists get our Phenomenal Concepts Wrong. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 89: 191–209.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Heil, J. (2003) From an Ontological Point of View. 2nd edn. New York, Oxford University Press. Reprinted 2009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Heil, J. (2004) Philosophy of Mind: A Contemporary Introduction. 2nd edn. Tyne and Wear, Routledge. Reprinted 2009.Google Scholar
  14. Heil, J. (2005) Dispositions. Synthese. 144: 343–356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Heil, J. (2010) Powerful Qualities. In: Marmodoro, A. (ed.) The Metaphysics of Powers: Their Grounding and Manifestations. New York, Routledge.Google Scholar
  16. Hill, C. (2009) Consciousness. New York, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Jacobs, J. (2011) Powerful Qualities, Not Pure Powers. The Monist. 94: 81–102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kripke, S. (1980) Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Levine, J. (2001) Purple Haze: the Puzzle of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds. Tyne and Wear, Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  21. Loar, B. (1990/1997) Phenomenal States. In: Block, N., Flanagan, O. and Güzeldere, G. (eds.) The Nature of Consciousness: Philosophical Debates. (2002). USA, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Locke, J. (1690/1978) An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. P.H. Nidditch. Oxford: Claredon Press.Google Scholar
  23. Lowe, E.J. (2000) Locke, Martin, and Substance. Philosophical Quarterly. 50: 499–514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Lowe, E. J. (2006) The Four Category Ontology: a Metaphysical Foundation for Natural Science. New York, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Martin, C. B. (1980) Substance Substantiated. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58: 3–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Martin, C. B. (1993) “Power for Realists.” In: Ontology, Causality and Mind: Essays in Honour of D. M. Armstrong. USA, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Martin, C. B. (2007) The Mind in Nature. New York, Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Martin, C. B. and Heil, J. (1998) Rules and Powers. Noûs. 32. Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, 12: 283–312.Google Scholar
  29. Martin, C. B. and Heil, J. (1999) The Ontological Turn. Midwest Studies in Philosophy. 23: 34–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Mellor, D. H. (1974) In Defence of Dispositions. The Philosophical Review.83: 157–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Papineau, D. (2002) Thinking About Consciousness. New York, Oxford Reprinted 2008.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Schroer, R. (2012) Can a Single Property Be Both Dispositional and Categorical? The “Partial Consideration Strategy”, Partially Considered. Metaphysica. doi:10.1007/s12133-012-0112-z.
  33. Shoemaker, S. (1980) Causality and Properties. In: Identity, Cause and Mind: Philosophical Essays: Expanded Edition. (2007). New York, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Shoemaker, S. (1998) Causal and Metaphysical Necessity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 79: 59–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Strawson, G. (2008) The Identity of the Categorical and the Dispositional. Analysis. 88: 271–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of DurhamDurhamUK

Personalised recommendations