Metaphysica

, Volume 9, Issue 1, pp 17–31 | Cite as

Initial Conditions and the ‘Open Systems’ Argument against Laws of Nature

Original Paper

Abstract

This article attacks ‘open systems’ arguments that because constant conjunctions are not generally observed in the real world of open systems we should be highly skeptical that universal laws exist. This work differs from other critiques of open system arguments against laws of nature by not focusing on laws themselves, but rather on the inference from open systems. We argue that open system arguments fail for two related reasons: 1) because they cannot account for the ‘systems’ central to their argument (nor the implied systems labeled ‘exogenous factors’ in relation to the system of interest) and 2) they are nomocentric, fixated on laws while ignoring initial and antecedent conditions that are able to account for systems and exogenous factors within a fundamentalist framework.

Keywords

Initial conditions Laws of nature Open systems Cartwright Quantum Decoherence 

References

  1. Albrecht, Andreas (1996), “How to Falsify Scenarios with Primordial Fluctuations from Inflation”, astro-ph/9612017.Google Scholar
  2. Anderson, Philip (2001), “Science: A ‘Dappled World’ or a ‘Seamless Web’?” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32 (3): 487–494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Auletta, Gennaro (2000), Foundations and Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics in the Light of a Critical-Historical Analysis of the Problems and of a Synthesis of the Results. Singapore: World Scientific.Google Scholar
  4. Barvinsky, A O, A Yu Kamenshchik, Kiefer, IV Mishakov (1999), “Decoherence in Quantum Cosmology at the Onset of Inflation”, Nuclear Physics B 551: 374–396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Beebee, Helen (2002), “Contingent Laws Rule”, Analysis 62: 252–255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bhaskar, Roy (1975), A Realist Theory of Science. Leeds: Leeds Books.Google Scholar
  7. Bird, Alexander (2002), “On Whether Some Laws are Necessary”, Analysis 62: 257–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Burock, Marc (2004), “Determinism and Causation Examples”, Philosophy of Science Archive, University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
  9. Callender, Craig (2004), “Measures, Explanations and the Past: Should ‘Special’ Initial Conditions Be Explained?”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55(2): 195–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Carter, Jessica (2005), “Individuation of Objects – A Problem for Structuralism?”, Synthese 143: 291–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Causey, Robert L. (1969), “Polanyi on Structure and Reduction”, Synthese 20: 230–237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cartwright, Nancy (1999), The Dappled World: A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Cartwright, Nancy (2002a), “In Favor of Laws that are not Ceteris Paribus After All”, Erkenntnis 57: 425–439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Cartwright, Nancy, (2002b), “The Limits of Causal Order, from Economics to Physics,” in Mäki, Uskali (ed.), Fact and Fiction in Economics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Churchman, CW, Ackoff, RL, and Arnoff, LE (1957). Introduction to Operations Research. Wiley, New York.Google Scholar
  16. Clarke, Kevin A. (1999), “Probabilistic Causality and Explanation in Political Science”, Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association September 2–5, 1999 Atlanta, GA.Google Scholar
  17. Drake, M.J., and K. Righter. (2002), “Determining the Composition of the Earth”, Nature 416: 39–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Earman, John (2004), “Determinism: What We Have Learned and What We Still Don’t Know”, in Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O’Rourke, and David Shier (eds.), Freedom and Determinism. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Earman, John, and Jesus Mosterin (1999), “A Critical Look at Inflationary Cosmology”, Philosophy of Science 66: 1–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Earman, John, and John Roberts (1999), “Ceteris Paribus, There is no Problem of Provisos”, Synthese 118: 439–478.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Earman, John, John Roberts, and Sheldon Smith (2002), “Ceteris Paribus Lost”, Erkenntnis 57: 281–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Frisch, Mathias (2004), “Laws and Initial Conditions”, Philosophy of Science, 71: 696–706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Gies, Douglas, and John Helsel (2005), “Ice Age Epochs and the Sun’s Path Through the Galaxy”, Astrophysical Journal 626: 844–848.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Hall, A.D., and R.E. Fagen (1956), “Definitions of a System”, in L. von Bertalanffy and A. Rapoport (eds.), General Systems: Volume I. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.Google Scholar
  25. Halonen, Ilpo, and Jaakko Hintikka (2005), “Toward a Theory of the Process of Explanation”, Synthese 143: 5–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Hoefer, Carl (2003), “For Fundamentalism”, Philosophy of Science 70: 1401–1412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hoffman (2001a), “The Moon and Plate Tectonics: Why We are Alone”, Space Daily (website) July 11, http://www.spacedaily.com/news/life-01x1.html.
  28. Hoffman (2001b), “Venus – What the Earth Would Have Been Like”, Space Daily (website) July 11, http://www.spacedaily.com/news/life-01x2.html.
  29. Humphreys, Paul (1989), The Chances of Explanation: Causal Explanation in the Social, Medical, and Physical Sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Kiefer, Claus, and David Polarski (1998), “Emergence of Classicality for Primordial Fluctuations: Concepts and Analogies”, Annalen der Physik 7: 137–158.Google Scholar
  31. Kiefer, Claus, David Polarski, and Alexei Starobinsky (1998a), “Quantum-to-Classical Transition for Fluctuations in the Early Universe”, International Journal of Modern Physics D 7: 455–462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Kiefer, Claus, Julien Lesgourgues, David Polarski, and Alexei Starobinsky (1998b), “The Coherence of Primordial Fluctuations Produced During Inflation”, Classical and Quantum Gravity 15: L67–L72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kline David A. and Carl A. Matheson (1986), “How the Laws of Physics Don’t Even Fib”, in Arthur Fine and Peter Machamer (eds.), PSA 1986: vol. 1. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 33–41.Google Scholar
  34. Lange, M (1993), “Natural Laws and the Problem of Provisos”, Erkenntnis 38: 233–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Lombardo, Fernando C (2005), “Influence Functional Approach to Decoherence During Inflation”, Brazilian Journal of Physics 35 (2B): 391–396.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Marchal J. H. (1975), “On the Concept of a System”, Philosophy of Science, 42: 448–468.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. McAllister, James (1999), “Universal Regularities and Initial Conditions in Newtonian Physics”, Synthese 120: 323–325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. McAllister, James (2004), “Absence of Contingency in the Newtonian Universe”, Foundations of Science 9: 191–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Morbidelli, A, J. Chambers, JI Lunine, JM Petit, F. Robert, GB Valsecchi, and K. Cyr, (2000), “Source Regions and Timescales for the Delivery of Water to the Earth”, Meteoritics and Planetary Science 35:1309–1320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Morowitz, Harold (2002), The Emergence of Everything: How the World Became Complex. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Norton, John (2003), “Causation as Folk Science”, Philosophy of Science Archive, University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar
  42. Poland, Jeffrey (1994), Physicalism: The Philosophical Foundations. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  43. Price, Huw (2002), “Boltzmann’s Time Bomb”, British Journal for the Philosophy Science 53, 1, 83–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Psillos, Stathis (2006), “Cartwright’s Realist Toil: From Entities to Capacities” in Luc Bovens and Stephan Hartmann (eds.), Nancy Cartwright’s Philosophy of Science. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  45. Resnik, Michael (1997), Mathematics as a Science of Patterns. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  46. Ruphy, Stéphanie (2003), “Is the World Really ‘Dappled’? A Response to Cartwright’s Charge against ‘Cross-Wise Reduction’”, Philosophy of Science, 70: 57–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Shapiro, Stewart (1997), Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Schlesinger, George N (1987), “Nomic Necessity and Contingency”, The Philosophical Quarterly 37: 379–391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Schlosshauer, Maximilian (2004), “Decoherence, the Measurement Problem, and Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics”, Review of Modern Physics 76(4): 1267–1305.Google Scholar
  50. Sklar, Lawrence (1991), “How Free Are Initial Conditions?” in Arthur Fine, Micky Forbes, and Linda Wessels (eds.), PSA 1990, vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 551564.Google Scholar
  51. Sklar, Lawrence (2003), “Dappled Theories in a Uniform World”, Philosophy of Science, 70: 424–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Smith, Sheldon R. (2001), “Models and the Unity of Classical Physics: Nancy Cartwright’s Dappled World”, Philosophy of Science, 68 (4): 456–475.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Spurrett, David (1999), The Completeness of Physics. Ph.D. Dissertation, Durban, South Africa: University of Natal.Google Scholar
  54. Spurrett, David (2001) “Cartwright on Laws of Composition”, International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15: 253–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Tegmark, Max (2004), “Parallel Universes”, in John D. Barrow, Paul C.W. Davies, and Charles L. Harper (eds.), Science and Ultimate Reality: Quantum Theory, Cosmology, and Complexity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Waldner, David (2002), “Anti Anti-Determinism: Or What Happens When Schrödinger’s Cat and Lorenz’s Butterfly Meet Laplace’s Demon in the Study of Political and Economic Development?”, Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, August 29–September 1. Boston MA.Google Scholar
  57. Whittle, Mark (2004), “The Sound of the Microwave Background”, American Astronomical Society Meeting 204.84.06.Google Scholar
  58. Wilson, Mark (1991), “Law along the Frontier: Differential Equations and Their Boundary Conditions” in Arthur Fine, Micky Forbes, and Linda Wessels (eds.), PSA 1990, vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 565–575.Google Scholar
  59. The Wright Center at Tufts University, “Cosmic Evolution”, Website. http://www.tufts.edu/as/wright_center/cosmic_evolution/index.html
  60. Yeghikyan, Ararat, and Hans Fahr (2003), “Consequences of the Solar System Passage Through Dense Interstellar Clouds”, Annales Geophysicae 21: 1263–1273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Yeghikyan, Ararat, and Hans Fahr (2004), “Terrestrial Atmospheric Effects Induced by Counterstreaming Dense Interstellar Cloud Material”, Astronomy and Astrophysics 425, 1113–1118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Zeh, Heinz-Dieter (2005), “How Decoherence May Solve the Measurement Problem”, unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
  63. Zurek, Wojciech (1991), “Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical”, Physics Today. 44 (10): 36–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Zurek, Wojciech (1998), “Decoherence, Einselection and the Existential Interpretation (the Rough Guide)”, Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, A. 356: 1793–1821.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Zurek, Wojciech (2003), “Decoherence, Einselection and the Quantum Origins of the Classical”, Reviews of Modern Physics 75: 715–775.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of CambridgeCambridgeUK
  2. 2.San FranciscoUSA

Personalised recommendations