Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

When is it Safe to Edit the Human Germline?

  • Original Research/Scholarship
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the fall of 2018 Jiankui He shocked the international community with the following announcement: two female babies, “Lulu” and “Nana,” whose germlines had been modified by the cutting edge, yet profoundly unsafe CRISPR-Cas9 technology had been born. This event galvanized policy makers and scientists to advocate for more explicit and firm regulation of human germline gene editing (GGE). Recent policy proposals attempt to integrate safety considerations and public input to identify specific types of diseases that may be safe targets for human GGE (Sarkar forthcoming; Guttinger. 2019. “Editing the Reactive Genome: Towards Postgenomic Ethics of Germline Editing.” Journal of Applied Philosophy. “Editing the Reactive Genome: Towards Postgenomic Ethics of Germline Editing.” Journal of Applied Philosophy. “Editing the Reactive Genome: Towards Postgenomic Ethics of Germline Editing.” Journal of Applied Philosophy; Lander et al., 2019). This paper argues these policy proposals are inadequate in different ways. While Sarkar (forthcoming) intends to incorporate input from the disability community for the purpose of deciding the value of human GGE, I argue that his strategy for doing so is inadequate. I’ll argue that an iterative, deliberative process is a more appropriate framework for allowing the disability community to inform policy on human GGE. Further policy proposals have been framed in terms of monogenetic or single-gene diseases (Guttinger. 2019. “Editing the Reactive Genome: Towards Postgenomic Ethics of Germline Editing.” Journal of Applied Philosophy. “Editing the Reactive Genome: Towards Postgenomic Ethics of Germline Editing.” Journal of Applied Philosophy. “Editing the Reactive Genome: Towards Postgenomic Ethics of Germline Editing.” Journal of Applied Philosophy; Lander et al., 2019). I argue that this way of conceptualizing disease is not what matters for deciding which disorders are viable candidates for human GGE. Instead, what matters is that (1) the disease in question must have (among its set of causes) genes that have a high degree of causal control with respect to the disease and (2) alternative nucleic acid sequences variants that are likely to produce traits deemed desirable must be identified. Previous policy proposals leave (2) unspecified. What conditions must be met for satisfying condition (2) should not be left to individual scientists to decide for themselves. The present proposal offers some guidance on this issue.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I am grateful to a blind reviewer for this observation.

  2. Jiankui He’s use of CRISPR-Cas9 to target the CCR5 genes in “Lulu” and “Nana” was performed at a time before the scientific community had proper understanding and control of the technology’s off-target effects. This was a violation of the temporary ban.

  3. Whether it is morally permissible to destroy human embryos for research purposes is a topic that will not be explored in this paper. With that said, a number of countries abide by the 14-day rule, which states that human embryos may not be kept alive beyond the 14th day after fertilization. Recently there have been calls to extend the number of days research on embryos is permitted (Appleby et al. 2018).

  4. Further developments in genome sequencing methods are also necessary for this sort of information to be possible.

  5. I am grateful to a blind referee for suggesting an ethical and conceptual contrast between human GGE and somatic stem cell gene therapy. The problem of unintended consequences is a more serious concern in the case of human GGE than in somatic cell gene therapy. This is due to the former introducing genomic modifications that will be inherited by all the cells of an individual, which in turn will influence development over the course of an individual’s lifetime. The problem of unintended consequences in the case of somatic stem cell therapy will be more contained to specific cell lineages and developmental stages and, thus, will be less serious than in the case of human GGE.

  6. A common concern expressed about human germline gene editing is its impact on human evolution (Doudna et al. 2017). The social, political, and epistemic considerations that are relevant for the evolutionary impact human germline gene editing might have on human populations deserves its own treatment. In this paper, the focus concerns the social, political, and epistemic considerations that are relevant for clinical trials with human germline gene editing. This is a noteworthy distinction as gene editing technologies alone are not sufficient for influencing human populations on an evolutionary scale. Further technological advancements (such as a method for editing the germlines of early-stage embryos in vivo) are likely to be needed for this sort of effect.

  7. Indeed, there is a burgeoning and unregulated market for implementing CRISPR technologies in fertility clinics in which a number of scientists are financially invested (Kirksey 2020).

  8. Broad societal consensus was originally one of two requirements for the responsible use of human germline gene editing included in the statement issued by the first International Summit on Human Gene Editing in 2015; however, this requirement has since been removed from more recent statements issued by the International Summit. (For criticism of this revision see Baylis 2019).

  9. This proposal is compatible with other communities from the public having a say in deciding the value of human germline gene editing.

  10. The view I am proposing is similar to the idea of a critical standpoint found in feminist epistemology (Wylie 2012) and Rolin’s (2015) concept of a scientific/intellectual movement.

  11. This characterization of ableism applies Alison Jaggar’s characterization of sexism to the issue of disability (Jaggar, 2008, pp. vii).

  12. The process outlined by Lander et al. (2019) is a more adequate model for enabling representatives of the public to inform the value judgments of human GGE; however, as I’ll argue in Sect. 5 their proposal falls short in other ways.

  13. Incorporating the perspectives of disabled individuals – especially individuals with cognitive impairments – requires its own theoretical framework as such individuals may not be able to communicate their perspective in a standard format (see Warren 2016). For this reason, it may be that caregivers and allies also be included as representatives of disabled communities.

  14. In fact, study of the CCR5-Δ32 mutation marked the beginning of this sort of integrative research program (see Jackson, 2015).

  15. The number of alternative variants will depend on whether one is removing a functional element entirely or simply replacing a deleterious functional element with a different one. Nevertheless, a sequence that is n-nucleotide bases long, will have ~ 4n number of possible alternative sequences from which scientists may choose. That is, for each nucleotide base in a sequence, there are four possibilities (adenine, thymine, guanine, cytosine). For an average protein coding gene, the number of alternative possible sequences is ~ 4900.

  16. This framework only works for genetic variants present in human populations. Whether it is safe to introduce variants from non-human species is a question that raises its own unique set of epistemic challenges and, thus, requires a separate treatment.

  17. Theoretical knowledge of how a gene edit is likely to influence health and development may (in some cases) be more justified than theoretical knowledge concerning how a novel pharmaceutical will influence humans. This is due to conditions (1) and (2) requiring scientists limit their theories and predictions to genetic determinants actually present in human populations. Consequently, researchers may have access to more evidence as to the outcomes of germline edits than researchers may have for a genuinely novel pharmaceutical drug.

  18. Sarkar (forthcoming) is sympathetic to the disability community having a say in human GGE policy and Lander et al. (2019) also advocate for public input on the matter. However, both sets of authors advocate for the restriction of human GGE to monogenetic diseases alone independent of what the disability community (or broader public) might have to say.

  19. Even though complex diseases may be candidates for human germline gene editing, there are pragmatic reasons to limit the number of genome edits to as few as possible. It is challenging enough to successfully introduce a single edit to germline cells so that the change is inherited by all cells of the organism. Performing multiple edits at this stage risks mosaic effects – an effect where only some cell lineages carry a desired edit and others don’t – as well as premature cell death and chromosomal rearrangement (Chari et al. 2017).

References

  • Alanis-Lobato, G., Zohren, J., McCarthy, A., Fogarty, N. M. E., Kubikova, N., Hardman, E., Greco, M., Wells, D., Turner, J. M. A., & Niakan, K. K. (2021). Frequent loss of heterozygosity in CRISPR cas9 edited early embryos. (pp. 9–1911).

  • Appleby, J. B., & Bredenoord, A. L. (2018). Should the 14-day rule for embryo research become the 28-day rule? EMBO Molecular Medicine, 10, e9437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ankeny, R. A., & Leonelli, S. (2011). What’s so special about model organisms? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 313, 323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baltimore, D., Berg, P., Botchan, M., Carroll, D., Charo, R. A., Church, G., Corn, J. E., Daley, G. Q., Doudna, J. A., Fenner, M., Greely, H. T., Jinek, M., Martin, G. S., Penhoet, E., Puck, J., Sternberg, S. H., Weissman, J. S., & Yamamoto, K. R. (2015). A prudent path forward for genomic engineering and germline gene modification. Science, 348, 6230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (2014). Valuing disability, causing disability. Ethics, 125(1), 88–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baylis, F. (2019). Altered inheritance: Crispr and the ethics of human genome editing. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blankmeyer, B. T. (2017). Gene therapy: A threat to the deaf community. Impact Ethics. https://impactethics.ca/2017/03/02/gene-therapy-a-threat-to-the-deaf-community/.

  • Cameron, A. (2017). Why I’m speaking about human genetic engineering as a black woman with disabilities. Gender and Societyhttps://medium.com/@C_G_S/why-im-speaking-about-human-genetic-engineering-as-a-black-woman-with-disabilities-7c6a869fa572.

  • Chari, R., & Church, G. M. (2017). Beyond editing to writing large genomes. Nature Reviews, 18, 749–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cokley, R. (2017). Please don’t edit me out. The Washington Posthttps://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/if-we-start-editing-genes-people-like-me-might-not-exist/2017/08/10/e9adf206-7d27-11e7-a669-b400c5c7e1cc_story.html.

  • Cullot, G., Boutin, J., Toutain, J., Prat, F., Pennamen, P., Rooryck, C., Teichmann, M., Rousseau, E., Lamrissi-Garcia, I., Guyonnet-Duperat, V., Bibeyran, A., Lalanne, M., Prouzet-Mauléon, V., Turcq, B., Ged, C., Blouin, J., Richard, E., Dabernat, S., Moreau-Gaudry, F., & Bedel, A. (2019). CRISPR-cas9 genome editing induces megabase-scale chromosomal truncations. Nature Communications, 10, 1136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, L. J. (1995). Enforcing normalcy: Disability, deafness, and the body. Verso Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doudna, J. A., & Charpentier, E. (2015). The new frontier of genome engineering with CRISPR-cas9. Science, 346, 6213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doudna, J. A., & Sternberg, S. H. (2017). A crack in creation: Gene editing and the unthinkable power to control evolution. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Genetics and Society. (2017). A conversation on disability, justice, and human genetic engineering. https://www.geneticsandsociety.org/multi-media/disability-justice-gene-editing-exploring-multiple-perspectives.

  • Glass, W. G., McDermott, D. H., Lim, J. K., Lekhong, S., Yu, S. F., Frank, W. A., Pape, J., Cheshier, R. C., & Murphy, P. M. (2006). CCR5 deficiency increases risk of symptomatic west nile virus infection. Journal of Experimental Medicine, 203(1), 35–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P., & Stotz, K. (2013). Genetics and philosophy: an introduction. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guttinger, S. (2019). Editing the reactive genome: Towards postgenomic ethics of germline editing. Journal of Applied Philosophy.

  • Gyngell, C., Douglas, T., & Savulescu, J. (2017). The ethics of germline gene editing. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 34, 4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heintzman, N. D., Hon, G. C., Hawkins, R. D., Kheradpour, P., Stark, A., Harp, L. F., Ye, Z., Lee, L. K., Stuart, R. K., Ching, C. W., Ching, K. A., Antosiewicz-Bourget, J. E., Liu, H., Zhang, X., Green, R. D., Lobanenkov, V. V., Stewart, R., Thomson, J. A., Crawford, G. E., Kellis, M., & Ren, B. (2009). Histone modifications at human enhancers reflect global cell-type-specific gene expression. Nature Letters, 459.

  • Heintzman, N. D., & Ren, B. (2007). The gateway to transcription: Identifying, characterizing and understanding promoters in the eukaryotic genome. Cellular and Molecular Life Sciences, 64, 386–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, M. W. (2015). The genealogy of a gene: Patents, hiv/aids, and race. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar, A. (2008). Just methods: An interdisciplinary feminist reader. Boulder: Paradigm Publishers

  • Keller, E. F. (2014). From gene action to reactive genomes. The Journal of Physiology, 592(11), 2423–2429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirksey, E. (2020). The mutant project. St. Martin’s Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lander, E. S., Baylis, F., Zhang, F., Charpentier, E., & Berg, P. (2019). Adopt a moratorium on heritable genome editing. Nature. 567

  • Lanphier, E., Urnov, F., Haecker, S. E., Werner, M., & Smolenski, J.  (2015). Don’t edit the human germline. Nature. 519

  • Ledford, H. (2020). CRISPR gene editing in human embryos wreaks chromosomal mahem. Nature. 583

  • Ma, H., Marti-Gutierrez, N., Park, S. W., Wu, J., Lee, Y., Suzuki, K., Koski, A., Ji, D., Hayama, T., Ahmed, R., Darby, H., Van Dyken, C., Li, Y., Kang, E., Park, A. R., Kim, D., Kim, S. T., Gong, J., Gu, Y., Xu, X., Battaglia, D., Krieg, S. A., Lee, D. M., Wu, D. H., Wolf, D. P., Heitner, S. B., Izpisua Belmonte, J. C., Amato, P., Kim, J. S., Kaul, S., & Mitalipov, S. (2017). Correction of a pathogenic gene mutation in human embryos. Nature Review.

  • Maier, R., Akbari, A., Wei, X., Patterson, N., Nielsen, R., & Reich, D. (2019). No statistical evidence for an effect of CCR5-δ32 on lifespan in the uk biobank cohort. Nature Medicine, 26, 178–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millstein, R. L. (2007). Hsp90-induced evolution: Adaptationist, neutralist, and developmental scenarios. Biological Theory, 2(4), 376–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. (2017). Human genome editing: Science, ethics, and governance. The National Academies Press

  • Ning, K. (2016). The village that AIDS tore apart: In the 1990s, unauthorized blood donation centers gave Henan Province residents more than just quick cash. http://www.sixthtone.com/news/897/the-village-that-aids-tore-apart/

  • Olson, S. (2015). International summit on human gene editing: A global discussion. National Academies of Science, Engineering and Medicine

  • O’Malley, M. A., Elliot, K. C., & Burian, R. M. (2010). From genetic to genomic regulation: Iterativity in microrna research. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 41, 407–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ormond, K. E., Mortlock, D. P., Scholes, D. T., Bombard, Y., Brody, L. C., Faucett, W. A., Garrison, N. A., Hercher, L., Isasi, R., Middleton, A., Musunuru, K., Shriner, D., Virani, A., & Young, C. E. (2017). Human germline genome editing. The American Journal of Human Genetics, 101, 167–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peng, R., Lin, G., & Li, J. (2015). Potential pitfalls of CRISPR/cas9-mediated genome editing. The FEBS Journal, 283, 1218–1231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Porter, T. M. (2018). Genetics in the madhouse: The unknown history of human heredity. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Qiao, J., & Feng, H. L. (2014). Assisted reproductive technology in China: Compliance and non-compliance. Translational Pedriatrics, 3(2), 91–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reimers, M. A., Craver, C., Dozmorov, M., Bacanu, S. A., & Kendler, K. S. (2019). The coherence problem: Finding meaning in GWAS complexity. Behavior Genetics, 49, 187–195.

  • Rolin, K. (2016). Values, standpoints, and scientific/intellectual movements. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 11–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L. N. (Forthcoming). Explanation in contexts of causal complexity: Lessons from psychiatric genetics. Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science, From Biological Practice to Scientific Metaphysics.

  • Sarewitz, D. (2015). CRISPR: Science can’t solve it. Nature. 522

  • Sarkar, S. (1998). Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (Forthcoming). A brave new eugenics: CRISPR and the human future.

  • Sheridan, C. (2011). Gene therapy finds its niche. Nature Biotechnology, 29(2), 121–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, K. B. (2016). Recognizing justice for citizens with cognitive disabilities. Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. (2018). The eugenic mind project. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolbring, G. (2003). Science and technology and the triple D (disease, disability, defect). In M. C. Roco & W. S. Bainbridge (Eds.), Converging technologies for improving human performance: Nanotechnology, biotechnology, information technology and cognitive science. The Netherlands: Kluser Academic Publishers.

  • Wong, A. (2017). Resisting abelism: Disabled people and human gene editing.  https://youtu.be/_vdeeR5DOSo.

  • Wu, Z., Chen, J., Scott, S. R., & McGoogan, J. M. (2019). History of the epidemic in China. Current HIV/AIDS Reports, 16, 458–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wylie, A. (2012). Feminist philosophy of science: Standpoint matters. Proceedings and Address of the American Philosophical Association, 86(2), 47–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xu, X., Yi, F., Pan, H., Duan, S., Ding, Z., Yuan, G., Qu, J., Zhang, H., & Liu, G. (2013). Progress and prospects in stem cell therapy. Acta Pharmacologica Sinica, 34, 741–746.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yanhai, W., Ran, H., Ran, G., & Arnade, L. (2009). Discrimination against People with HIV/AIDS in China. The Equal Rights Review. 4.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I have Anya Plutynski, Lauren Ross, Zina Ward, Katie Kendig, and Stephan Guttinger to thank for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Janella Baxter.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baxter, J. When is it Safe to Edit the Human Germline?. Sci Eng Ethics 27, 43 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-021-00320-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-021-00320-x

Navigation