Advertisement

Science and Engineering Ethics

, Volume 23, Issue 1, pp 105–120 | Cite as

The Ethics of Doing Ethics

  • Sven Ove HanssonEmail author
Original Paper

Abstract

Ethicists have investigated ethical problems in other disciplines, but there has not been much discussion of the ethics of their own activities. Research in ethics has many ethical problems in common with other areas of research, and it also has problems of its own. The researcher’s integrity is more precarious than in most other disciplines, and therefore even stronger procedural checks are needed to protect it. The promotion of some standpoints in ethical issues may be socially harmful, and even our decisions as to which issues we label as “ethical” may have unintended and potentially harmful social consequences. It can be argued that ethicists have an obligation to make positive contributions to society, but the practical implications of such an obligation are not easily identified. This article provides an overview of ethical issues that arise in research into ethics and in the application of such research. It ends with a list of ten practical proposals for how these issues should be dealt with.

Keywords

Ethics in practice Code of ethics Ethics of ethics Applied ethics Publication ethics Plagiarism Integrity of ethics Consultancy Research funding 

References

  1. Agich, G. J. (1990). Clinical ethics: A role theoretic look. Social Science and Medicine, 30, 389–399.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Anon, (2013). Retraction note: The ‘strong’ versus ‘weak’ premise of stakeholder legitimacy and the rhetorical perspective of diffusion. Journal of Business Ethics, 113, 561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Baker, R. (2009). A history of codes of ethics for bioethicists. In L. A. Eckenwiler & F. G. Cohn (Eds.), The ethics of bioethics: Mapping the moral landscape (pp. 24–40). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Beauchamp, T. L. (2005). What can a model professional code for bioethics hope to achieve? American Journal of Bioethics, 5(5), 42–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Berkowitz, P. (2000). The utilitarian horrors of Peter Singer. Other People’s Mothers. New Republic 27–37.Google Scholar
  6. Brown, A. S., & Halliday, H. E. (1991). Cryptomnesia and source memory difficulties. American Journal of Psychology, 104, 475–490.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Chroust, A.-H. (1961). Charges of Phiilosophical Plagiarism in Greek Antiquity. Modern Schoolman, 38, 219–237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Cicero. (2001). On moral ends. In J. Annas (Ed.), Cambridge texts in the history of philosophy (R. Woolf, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Cohen, M. (2001). Was Wittgenstein a plagiarist? Philosophy, 76, 451–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cummins, D. (2002). The professional status of bioethics consultation. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 23(1), 19–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Debruin, D. A. (2009). Ethics on the inside? In L. A. Eckenwiler & F. G. Cohn (Eds.), The ethics of bioethics: Mapping the moral landscape (pp. 162–169). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Defeldre, A.-C. (2005). Inadvertent plagiarism in everyday life. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 19, 1033–1040.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Eichacker, P. Q., Natanson, C., & Danner, R. L. (2006). Surviving sepsis—Practice guidelines, marketing campaigns, and Eli Lilly. New England Journal of Medicine, 355(16), 1640–1642.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Elliott, C. (2001). Throwing a bone to the watchdog. Hastings Center Report, 31(2), 9–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Ferber, R., & Zentner, M. R. (1993). ‘Und werden wieder hell’—Nietzsches Mark Aurel. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 75, 219–224.Google Scholar
  16. Glock, H. J. (1994). The Euthanasia Debate in Germany—What’s the Fuss? Journal of Applied Philosophy, 11(2), 213–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Glock, H.-J. (2011). Doing good by splitting hairs? Analytic philosophy and applied ethics. Journal of applied philosophy, 28(3), 225–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Goldstein, L. (1999). Wittgenstein’s Ph.D. viva—A re-creation. Philosophy, 74, 499–513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Goldstein, L. (2002). How original a work is the Tractatus logico-philosophicus? Philosophy, 77, 421–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Grunwald, A. (2010). From speculative nanoethics to explorative philosophy of nanotechnology. Nanoethics, 4(2), 91–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Hansson, S. O. (2007). Philosophical problems in cost-benefit analysis. Economics and Philosophy, 23, 163–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hansson, S. O. (2008). The obligations of philosophers. Theoria, 74(3), 179–180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hansson, S. O. (2009). Ethics beyond application. In T. Takala, P. Herissone-Kelly, & S. Holm (Eds.), Cutting through the surface: Philosophical approaches to bioethics (pp. 19–28). Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi.Google Scholar
  24. Harkrider, L. N., MacDougall, A. E., Bagdasarov, Z., Johnson, J. F., Mumford, M. D., Connelly, S., & Devenport, L. D. (2014). Retracted article: Improving case-based ethics training: How modeling behaviors and forecasting influence effectiveness. Science and Engineering Ethics, 20, 299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Hintikka, J. (1993). Ludwig’s apple tree: On the philosophical relations between Wittgenstein and the Vienna circle. In F. Stadler, et al. (Eds.), Scientific philosophy: Origins and developments (pp. 27–46). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Isenberg, J. S. (2014). Retraction note to: Surgical research and the ethics of being first. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 48, 171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Jung, C. G. ([1905] 1966). “Kryptomnesie”, Die Zukunft 13:325–334. In Gesammelte Werke, vol I. Zürich: Walter Verlag.Google Scholar
  28. Kant, I. (1912). Kant’s gesammelte Schriften (Vol. 8). Berlin: Königlich Preussichen Akademie der Wissenschaften.Google Scholar
  29. Kittay, E. F. (2009). The personal is philosophical is political: A philosopher and mother of a cognitively disabled person sends notes from the battlefield. Metaphilosophy, 40, 606–627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Kuhn, T. S. (1974). Logic of discovery or psychology of research? In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.) The Philosophy of Karl Popper, The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. xiv, book i, pp. 798–819. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  31. Leslie, S.-J., Cimpian, A., Meyer, M., & Freeland, E. (2015). Expectations of brilliance underlie gender distributions across academic disciplines. Science, 347(6219), 262–265.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Markowitz, E. M. (2012). Is climate change an ethical issue? Examining young adults’ beliefs about climate and morality. Climatic Change, 114(3–4), 479–495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Marsh, R. L., & Bower, G. H. (1993). Eliciting cryptomnesia: Unconscious plagiarism in a puzzle task. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 19, 673–688.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Marsh, R. L., Landau, J. D., & Hicks, J. L. (1997). Contributions of inadequate source monitoring to unconscious plagiarism during idea generation. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 23, 886–897.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Michalos, A. C. (2010). Erratum to: Modern business ethics research: Concept, theory and relationships. Journal of Business Ethics, 93, 495.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Michalos, A. C. (2013). Retraction note: Corporate social responsibility in purchasing and supply chain. Journal of Business Ethics, 113, 183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Morreim, E. H. (2009). Ties without tethers: bioethics corporate relations in the AbioCor artificial heart trial. In L. A. Eckenwiler & F. G. Cohn (Eds.), The ethics of bioethics: Mapping the moral landscape (pp. 181–190). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Nordmann, A. (2007). If and then: A critique of speculative nanoethics. Nanoethics, 1, 31–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Nordmann, A., & Rip, A. (2009). Mind the gap revisited. Nature Nanotechnology, 4, 273–274.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Olbert, F. (2015). Phil.Cologne lädt Philosoph Peter Singer wieder aus. Kölner Stadt-Anzeiger, May 28.Google Scholar
  41. Passmore, J. (1965). The idea of a history of philosophy. History and Theory, 5(Suppl. 5), 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Scarre, G. (1994). Epicurus as a Forerunner of Utilitarianism. Utilitas, 6, 219–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Sharpe, V. A. (2002). Science, bioethics, and the public interest: On the need for transparency. Hastings Center Report, 32(3), 23–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Sharpe, V. A. (2009). Strategic disclosure requirements and the ethics of bioethics. In L. A. Eckenwiler & F. G. Cohn (Eds.), The ethics of bioethics: Mapping the moral landscape (pp. 170–180). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Singer, P. (1990). Bioethics and academic freedom. Bioethics, 4, 33–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Smith, C. U. M. (1998). Descartes’ visit to the town library, or how Augustinian is Descartes’ neurophysiology? Journal of the History of the Neurosciences, 7, 93–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Streeck, N. (2015). Èin Embryo hat kein Recht auf Leben. [Interview with Peter Singer], Neue Zürcher Zeitung, May 24.Google Scholar
  48. Takala, T. (2005). Demagogues, firefighters, and window dressers: Who are we and what should we be? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 14(4), 385–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Tsui, A. S., & Lewin, A. Y. (2014). Retraction statement for ‘Ethics and Integrity of the Publishing Process: Myths, Facts, and a Roadmap’ by Marshall Schminke and Maureen L. Ambrose. Management and Organization Review, 10, 157–162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Turner, L. (2009). Global health inequalities and bioethics. In L. A. Eckenwiler & F. G. Cohn (Eds.), The ethics of bioethics: Mapping the moral landscape (pp. 229–240). Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  51. van Es, R. (1993). On being a consultant in business ethics. Business Ethics: A European Review, 2, 228–232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. van Luijk, H. J. L. (1993). Ethical corporate consultancy. Business Ethics: A European Review, 2, 149–151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Wiesemann, C. (1991). Josef Dietl und der therapeutische Nihilismus: zum historischen und politischen Hintergrund einer medizinischen These, volume 28 of Marburger Schriften zur Medizingeschichte. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang.Google Scholar
  54. Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  55. Wittgenstein, L. (1953) Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Division of PhilosophyRoyal Institute of Technology (KTH)StockholmSweden

Personalised recommendations