Science and Engineering Ethics

, Volume 18, Issue 1, pp 13–34 | Cite as

“Ain’t No One Here But Us Social Forces”: Constructing the Professional Responsibility of Engineers

Original paper

Abstract

There are many ways to avoid responsibility, for example, explaining what happens as the work of the gods, fate, society, or the system. For engineers, “technology” or “the organization” will serve this purpose quite well. We may distinguish at least nine (related) senses of “responsibility”, the most important of which are: (a) responsibility-as-causation (the storm is responsible for flooding), (b) responsibility-as-liability (he is the person responsible and will have to pay), (c) responsibility-as-competency (he’s a responsible person, that is, he’s rational), (d) responsibility-as-office (he’s the responsible person, that is, the person in charge), and (e) a responsibility-as-domain-of-tasks (these are her responsibilities, that is, the things she is supposed to do). For all but the causal sense of responsibility, responsibility may be taken (in a relatively straightforward sense)—and generally is. Why then would anyone want to claim that certain technologies make it impossible to attribute responsibility to engineers (or anyone else)? In this paper, I identify seven arguments for that claim and explain why each is fallacious. The most important are: (1) the argument from “many hands”, (2) the argument from individual ignorance, and (3) the argument from blind forces. Each of these arguments makes the same fundamental mistake, the assumption that a certain factual situation, being fixed, settles responsibility, that is, that individuals, either individually or by some group decision, cannot take responsibility. I conclude by pointing out the sort of decisions (and consequences) engineers have explicitly taken responsibility for and why taking responsibility for them is rational, all things considered. There is no technological bar to such responsibility.

Keywords

Engineer Responsibility Liability Accountability Causation 

References

  1. Alpern, K. (1983). Moral responsibility for engineers. Business and Professional Ethics Journal, 2, 39–48.Google Scholar
  2. American Institute of Electrical Engineers. (1912). Code of ethics (March 8). http://ethics.iit.edu/publication/CODE–Exxon%20Module.pdf. Accessed July 22, 2010.
  3. Arthur, J., & Shaw, W. H. (Eds.). (2006). Readings in the philosophy of law (4th ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  4. Baumgartner, M. (2008). Regularity theories reassessed. Philosophia, 36, 327–354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bayles, M. D. (1979). A problem of clean hands. Social Theory and Practice, 5, 165–181.Google Scholar
  6. Bayles, M. D. (1986). Reply to Davis. In Davis & Elliston (1986) (pp. 458–460).Google Scholar
  7. Boniolo, G., & De Anna, G. (2006). The four faces of omission: Ontology, terminology, epistemology, and ethics. Philosophical Explorations, 19, 277–293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bovens, M. (1998). The quest for responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Bucciarelli, L. L. (2002). Is idiot proof safe enough? Applied Philosophy, 2, 49–57.Google Scholar
  10. Cane, P. (2002). Responsibility in law and morality. Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
  11. Davis, M. (1986a). The right to refuse a case. In Davis & Elliston (1986) (pp. 441–457).Google Scholar
  12. Davis, M. (1986b). Rejoinder to Bayles. In Davis & Elliston (1986) (pp. 451–464).Google Scholar
  13. Davis, M. (1997). Better communications between engineers and managers: Some ways to prevent ethically hard choices. Science and Engineering Ethics, 3, 171–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Davis, M. (1998). Thinking like an engineer: Essays in the ethics of a profession. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Davis, M., & Elliston, F. (Eds.). (1986). Ethics and the legal profession. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
  16. Dowe, P. (2004). Causes are physically connected to their effects; Why preventers and omissions are not causes. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 189–196). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  17. Feinberg, J. (1970). Doing and deserving. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Florman, S. C. (1978). Moral blueprints. Harper’s, 257, 311–323.Google Scholar
  19. Glover, J. (1975). It makes no difference whether or not i do it: Part 1. Aristotelian Society: Supplementary Volume, 49, 171–190.Google Scholar
  20. Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The concept of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Hart, H. L. A. (1968). Punishment and responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Hart, H. L. A., & Honoré, A. M. (1973). Causation in the Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. IEEE. (2006). Code of ethics. http://www.ieee.org/membership_services/membership/ethics_code.html. Accessed July 22, 2010.
  24. Kranzberg, M. (Ed.). (1980). Ethics in an age of pervasive technology. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  25. Kuflik, A. (1999). Computers in control: Rational transfer of authority or irresponsible abdication of autonomy? Ethics and Information Technology, 1, 173–184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Kutz, C. (2002). Responsibility. In J. Coleman & S. Shapiro (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence and philosophy of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Ladd, J. (1982). Philosophical remarks on professional responsibility in organizations. The International Journal of Applied Philosophy, 1, 58–70.Google Scholar
  28. Lynch, T., & Kline, Ronald. (2000). Engineering practice and engineering ethics. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 25, 195–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. McGrath, S. (2005). Causation by omission: A dilemma. Philosophical Studies, 123, 125–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Miller, D. (2005). Distributing responsibilities. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 9, 453–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Nissenbaum, H. (1996). Accountability in a computerized society. Science and Engineering Ethics, 2, 25–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. NSPE. (2010). Code of ethics for engineers. National Society of Professional Engineers, http://www.nspe.org/Ethics/CodeofEthics/index.html. Accessed July 22.
  33. Pundik, A. (2007). Can one deny both causation by omission and causal pluralism? The case of legal causation. In Russo & J. Williamson (2007) (pp. 379–412).Google Scholar
  34. Russo, F., & Williamson, J. (Eds.). (2007). Causality and probability in the sciences. London, UK: College Publications.Google Scholar
  35. Schnädelbach, H. (1980). Is technology ethically neutral? In Kranzberg (1980).Google Scholar
  36. Scott-Taggart, M. J. (1975). It makes no difference whether or not i do it: Part 2. Aristotelian Society: Supplementary Volume, 49, 191–209.Google Scholar
  37. Sher, G. (2006). Out of control. Ethics, 116, 285–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Sundström, P. (1998). Interpreting the notion that technology is value-neutral. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 1, 41–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Swierstra, T., & Jelsma, J. (2006). Practice responsibility without moralism in technoscientific design. Science, Technology, and Human Values, 31, 309–332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Thompson, D. E. (1987). Political ethics and public office. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Winner, L. (1995). The enduring dilemmas of autonomous technique. Bulletin of Science, Technology & Society, 15, 67–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Wiseman, G. (1980). The powerlessness of engineers. In Kranzberg (1980).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Humanities Department, Center for the Study of Ethics in the ProfessionsIllinois Institute of TechnologyChicagoUSA

Personalised recommendations