Science and Engineering Ethics

, Volume 13, Issue 1, pp 69–82 | Cite as

A case for a duty to feed the hungry: GM plants and the third world

Original Paper

Abstract

This article is concerned with a discussion of the plausibility of the claim that GM technology has the potential to provide the hungry with sufficient food for subsistence. Following a brief outline of the potential applications of GM in this context, a history of the green revolution and its impact will be discussed in relation to the current developing world agriculture situation. Following a contemporary analysis of malnutrition, the claim that GM technology has the potential to provide the hungry with sufficient nourishment will be discussed within the domain of moral philosophy to determine whether there exists a moral obligation to pursue this end if and only if the technology proves to be relatively safe and effective. By using Peter Singer’s duty of moral rescue, I argue that we have a moral duty to assist the third world through the distribution of such GM plants. I conclude the paper by demonstrating that my argument can be supported by applying a version of the Precautionary Principle on the grounds that doing nothing might be worse for the current situation.

Keywords

Genetically modified food Duty of rescue Malnutrition Green revolution Precautionary principle 

References

  1. 1.
    Bouis, B. (1996). Enrichment of food staples through plant breeding. Nutrition Reviews, 54(5), 131–137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Christou, P., & Twyman, M. (2004) The potential of genetically enhanced plants to address food insecurity. Nutrition Research Reviews, 17, 23–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    Cullity, G. (1994) International aid and the scope of kindness. Ethics, 105, 99–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Davies, W. P. (2003). An historical perspective from the green revolution to the gene revolution. Nutrition Reviews, 61(6), s124–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Estrella, H. et al. (2001). Genetically modified crops—hope for developing countries. Embo Reports, 2, 256–258.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Evenson, R. E., & Gollin, D. (2003). Assessing the impact of the green revolution, 1960 to 2000. Science, 300, 758–762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Foster, P., & Leathers, H. D. (1999). The world food problem: Tackling the causes of undernutrition in the third world. Colorado: Lynne Rienner Publishers.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Goff, S. A., & Salmeron, J. M. (2004). Back to the future of cereals. Scientific American, 291(2), 26–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Millennium Project Task Force on Hunger (2004). Halving Hunger by 2015: A framework for action. Interim Report. New York.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Nuffield Council on Bioethics (2004). The use of genetically modified crops in developing countries: A follow-up discussion paper. London.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Parker, J. (1998) Precautionary principle. In R. Chadwick (Ed.), Encyclopedia of applied ethics (pp. 633–641). San Diego: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Singer, P. (2002). Famine, affluence, and morality. In H. LaFollette (Ed.), Ethics in practice: An anthology (pp. 572–581). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    Tripp, R. (2001). Twixt cup and lip—biotechnology and resource-poor farmers. Nature Biotechnology, 19, 93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    University of Toronto Joint Centre for Bioethics (2002) Top 10 biotechnologies for improving health in developing countries. Toronto: University of Toronto.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.The School of History, Philosophy, Religion and ClassicsThe University of QueenslandBrisbaneAustralia
  2. 2.ARC Centre of Excellence for Integrative Legume ResearchThe University of QueenslandBrisbaneAustralia

Personalised recommendations