Israel Journal of Mathematics

, Volume 216, Issue 2, pp 905–955 | Cite as

The weakness of being cohesive, thin or free in reverse mathematics

Article

Abstract

Informally, a mathematical statement is robust if its strength is left unchanged under variations of the statement. In this paper, we investigate the lack of robustness of Ramsey’s theorem and its consequence under the frameworks of reverse mathematics and computable reducibility. To this end, we study the degrees of unsolvability of cohesive sets for different uniformly computable sequence of sets and identify different layers of unsolvability. This analysis enables us to answer some questions of Wang about how typical sets help computing cohesive sets.

We also study the impact of the number of colors in the computable reducibility between coloring statements. In particular, we strengthen the proof by Dzhafarov that cohesiveness does not strongly reduce to stable Ramsey’s theorem for pairs, revealing the combinatorial nature of this nonreducibility and prove that whenever k is greater than l, stable Ramsey’s theorem for n-tuples and k colors is not computably reducible to Ramsey’s theorem for n-tuples and l colors. In this sense, Ramsey’s theorem is not robust with respect to his number of colors over computable reducibility. Finally, we separate the thin set and free set theorem from Ramsey’s theorem for pairs and identify an infinite decreasing hierarchy of thin set theorems in reverse mathematics. This shows that in reverse mathematics, the strength of Ramsey’s theorem is very sensitive to the number of colors in the output set. In particular, it enables us to answer several related questions asked by Cholak, Giusto, Hirst and Jockusch.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. [1]
    J. Avigad, E. T. Dean and J. Rute, Algorithmic randomness, reverse mathematics, and the dominated convergence theorem, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 163 (2012), 1854–1864.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  2. [2]
    L. Bienvenu, L. Patey and P. Shafer, On the logical strengths of partial solutions to mathematical problems, ArXiv e-prints (2014).Google Scholar
  3. [3]
    A. Bovykin and A. Weiermann, The strength of infinitary Ramseyan principles can be accessed by their densities, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, to appear (2005).Google Scholar
  4. [4]
    V. Brattka and T. Rakotoniaina, On the Uniform Computational Content of Ramsey’s Theorem, ArXiv e-prints (2015).Google Scholar
  5. [5]
    P. A. Cholak, M. Giusto, J. L. Hirst and C. G. Jockusch, Free sets and reverse mathematics, in Reverse mathematics 2001, Lect. Notes Log., Vol. 21, Assoc. Symbol. Logic, La Jolla, CA, 2005, pp. 104–119.Google Scholar
  6. [6]
    P. A. Cholak, C. G. Jockusch and T. A. Slaman, On the strength of Ramsey’s theorem for pairs, J. Symbolic Logic 66 (2001), 1–55.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  7. [7]
    C. T. Chong, S. Lempp and Y. Yang, On the role of the collection principle for S02-formulas in second-order reverse mathematics, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 138 (2010), 1093–1100.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  8. [8]
    C. T. Chong, T. A. Slaman and Y. Yang, The metamathematics of stable Ramsey’s theorem for pairs, J. Amer. Math. Soc. 27 (2014), 863–892.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  9. [9]
    F. G. Dorais, D. D. Dzhafarov, J. L. Hirst, J. R. Mileti and P. Shafer, On uniform relationships between combinatorial problems, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 368 (2016), 1321–1359.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  10. [10]
    D. D. Dzhafarov, Cohesive avoidance and arithmetical sets, ArXiv e-prints (2012).Google Scholar
  11. [11]
    D. D. Dzhafarov, Strong reductions between combinatorial principles, Journal of Symbolic Logic, to appear.Google Scholar
  12. [12]
    D. D. Dzhafarov, Cohesive avoidance and strong reductions, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 143 (2015), 869–876.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  13. [13]
    R. Friedberg, A criterion for completeness of degrees of unsolvability, J. Symb. Logic 22 (1957), 159–160.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  14. [14]
    H. M. Friedman, Fom:53:free sets and reverse math and fom:54:recursion theory and dynamics, Available at https://www.cs.nyu.edu/pipermail/fom/.Google Scholar
  15. [15]
    H. M. Friedman, Boolean relation theory and incompleteness, Lecture Notes in Logic, to appear (2013).Google Scholar
  16. [16]
    N. Greenberg and J. S. Miller, Lowness for Kurtz randomness, J. Symbolic Logic 74 (2009), 665–678.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  17. [17]
    D. R. Hirschfeldt, Slicing the truth, Lecture Notes Series. Institute for Mathematical Sciences. National University of Singapore, Vol. 28, World Scientific Publishing Co. Pte. Ltd., Hackensack, NJ, 2015, On the computable and reverse mathematics of combinatorial principles, Edited and with a foreword by Chitat Chong, Qi Feng, Theodore A. Slaman, W. Hugh Woodin and Yue Yang.Google Scholar
  18. [18]
    D. R. Hirschfeldt and C. G. Jockusch, On notions of computability theoretic reduction between 12 principles, To appear.Google Scholar
  19. [19]
    D. R. Hirschfeldt and R. A. Shore, Combinatorial principles weaker than Ramsey’s theorem for pairs, J. Symbolic Logic 72 (2007), 171–206.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  20. [20]
    C. G. Jockusch, A. Lewis and J. B. Remmel, 01-classes and Rado’s selection principle, J. Symbolic Logic 56 (1991), 684–693.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  21. [21]
    C. Jockusch and F. Stephan, A cohesive set which is not high, Math. Logic Quart. 39 (1993), 515–530.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  22. [22]
    C. G. Jockusch, Ramsey’s theorem and recursion theory, J. Symbolic Logic 37 (1972), 268–280.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  23. [23]
    C. G. Jockusch, Degrees of generic sets, in Recursion theory: its generalisation and applications (Proc. Logic Colloq., Univ. Leeds, Leeds, 1979), London Math. Soc. Lecture Note Ser., Vol. 45, Cambridge Univ. Press, Cambridge-New York, 1980, pp. 110–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. [24]
    C. G. Jockusch and R. I. Soare, 01 classes and degrees of theories, Trans. Amer. Math. Soc. 173 (1972), 33–56.MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  25. [25]
    S. M. Kautz, Degrees of random sets, ProQuest LLC, Ann Arbor, MI, 1991, Thesis (Ph.D.)–Cornell University.Google Scholar
  26. [26]
    S. M. Kautz, An improved zero-one law for algorithmically random sequences, Theoret. Comput. Sci. 191 (1998), 185–192.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  27. [27]
    M. Khan and J. S. Miller, Forcing with bushy trees, Preprint (2014).Google Scholar
  28. [28]
    B. Kjos-Hanssen, Infinite subsets of random sets of integers, Math. Res. Lett. 16 (2009), 103–110.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  29. [29]
    M. Lerman, R. Solomon and H. Towsner, Separating principles below Ramsey’s theorem for pairs, J. Math. Log. 13 (2013), 1350007, 44.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  30. [30]
    J. Liu, RT22 does not imply WKL0, J. Symbolic Logic 77 (2012), 609–620.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. [31]
    J. R. Mileti, Partition theorems and computability theory, ProQuest LLC, Ann Arbor, MI, 2004, Thesis (Ph.D.)–University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.MATHGoogle Scholar
  32. [32]
    W. Miller and D. A. Martin, The degrees of hyperimmune sets, Z. Math. Logik Grundlagen Math. 14 (1968), 159–166.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  33. [33]
    A. Montalbán, Open questions in reverse mathematics, Bull. Symbolic Logic 17 (2011), 431–454.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  34. [34]
    L. Patey, Controlling iterated jumps of solutions to combinatorial problems, Computability, to appear.Google Scholar
  35. [35]
    L. Patey, Combinatorial weaknesses of Ramseyan principles, In preparation (2015), Available athttp://ludovicpatey.com/media/research/combinatorial-weaknesses-draft.pdf.Google Scholar
  36. [36]
    L. Patey, Degrees bounding principles and universal instances in reverse mathematics, Ann. Pure Appl. Logic 166 (2015), 1165–1185.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  37. [37]
    L. Patey, Iterative forcing and hyperimmunity in reverse mathematics, in Evolving computability, Lecture Notes in Comput. Sci., Vol. 9136, Springer, Cham, 2015, pp. 291–301.Google Scholar
  38. [38]
    T. Rakotoniaina, The computational strength of Ramseys theorem, 2015, Thesis (Ph.D.)–University of Cape Town.Google Scholar
  39. [39]
    J. G. Rosenstein, Linear orderings, Pure and Applied Mathematics, Vol. 98, Academic Press, Inc.[Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, Publishers], New York-London, 1982.Google Scholar
  40. [40]
    D. Seetapun and T. A. Slaman, On the strength of Ramsey’s theorem, Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 36 (1995), 570–582, Special Issue: Models of arithmetic.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  41. [41]
    J. R. Shoenfield, On degrees of unsolvability, Ann. of Math. (2) 69 (1959), 644–653.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  42. [42]
    S. G. Simpson, An extension of the recursively enumerable Turing degrees, J. Lond. Math. Soc. (2) 75 (2007), 287–297.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  43. [43]
    S. G. Simpson, Subsystems of second order arithmetic, second ed., Perspectives in Logic, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge; Association for Symbolic Logic, Poughkeepsie, NY, 2009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. [44]
    F. Stephan, Martin-Löf random and PA-complete sets, in Logic Colloquium’ 02, Lect. Notes Log., Vol. 27, Assoc. Symbol. Logic, La Jolla, CA, 2006, pp. 342–348.Google Scholar
  45. [45]
    M. van Lambalgen, The axiomatization of randomness, J. Symbolic Logic 55 (1990), 1143–1167.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  46. [46]
    W. Wang, Omitting cohesive sets, Nanjing Daxue Xuebao Shuxue Bannian Kan 30 (2013), 40–47.MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  47. [47]
    W. Wang, Some logically weak Ramseyan theorems, Adv. Math. 261 (2014), 1–25.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  48. [48]
    W. Wang, The Definability Strength of Combinatorial Principles, ArXiv e-prints (2014).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Hebrew University of Jerusalem 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.ParisFrance

Personalised recommendations