Sophia

pp 1–19 | Cite as

Moral Agency and the Paradox of Self-Interested Concern for the Future in Vasubandhu’s Abhidharmakośabhāṣya

Article
  • 12 Downloads

Keywords

Agency Self Personal identity Buddhism Vasubandhu Abhidharmakośabhāṣya 

Notes

Acknowledgements

The article was written with the kind support of a research grant by the Deutscher Akademischer Austauschdienst (DAAD). I would like to thank Charles E. Snyder, Roy Tzohar, David Weinstein, and Michael Zimmermann for their helpful comments on earlier drafts. Thanks go as well to two anonymous reviewers.

References

Primary Sources

  1. AKBh Pradhan, P. (Ed.), (1975). Abhidharma-kośabhāṣya of Vasubandhu, revised by A. Haldar. Patna: K. P. Jayaswal Research Institute.Google Scholar
  2. AKVy Shastri, Swami Dwarikadas (Ed.), (1970–1973). Abhidharmakośa & Bhāṣya of Acharya Vasubandhu with Sphuṭārthā Commentary of Ācārya Yaśomitra. Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati.Google Scholar
  3. AKBhT Zhu-chen Tshul-khrims-rin-chen (Ed.) (1985). sDe-dge Bstan-’gyur. Vols. 140 & 141. #4090. Delhi: Delhi Karmapae Choedhey, Gyalwae Sungrab Partun Khang. Accessed through www.aciparchive.org and www.tbrc.org.

Secondary Sources

  1. Adam, M. T. (2005). Groundwork for a metaphysic of Buddhist morals: A new analysis of puñña and kusala, in light of sukka. Journal of Buddhist Ethics, 12, 62–85.Google Scholar
  2. Alt, W. (1980). There is no paradox of desire in Buddhism. Philosophy East and West, 30(4), 521–528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bryant, E. F. (2014). Agency in Sāṃkhya and Yoga: The unchangeability of the eternal. In M. R. Dasti & E. F. Bryant (Eds.), Free will, agency and selfhood in Indian philosophy (pp. 16–40). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Cardona, G. (2014). Pāṇinian grammarians on agency and independence. In M. R. Dasti & E. F. Bryant (Eds.), Free will, agency and selfhood in Indian philosophy (pp. 85–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Chadha, M. (2017). No-self and the phenomenology of agency. Phenomenology and Cognitive Sciences, 16(2), 187–205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Clayton, B. (2001). Compassion as a matter of fact: The argument from no-self to selflessness in Śāntideva’s Śikṣāsamuccaya. Contemporary Buddhism, 2(1), 83–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Dasti, M. R. (2014a). Nyāya’s self as agent and knower. In M. R. Dasti & E. F. Bryant (Eds.), Free will, agency and selfhood in Indian philosophy (pp. 112–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Dasti, M. R. (2014b). Introduction. In M. R. Dasti & E. F. Bryant (Eds.), Free will, agency and selfhood in Indian philosophy (pp. 1–15). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Dhammajoti, Bhikkhu K. L. (2007) Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma, Third Revised Edition. Hong Kong: Centre of Buddhist Studies, The University of Honk Kong.Google Scholar
  10. Duerlinger, J. (2003). Indian Buddhist theories of persons: Vasubandhu’s “refutation of the theory of a self”. London; New York: Routledge Curzon. Google Scholar
  11. Ganeri, J. (2007). The concealed art of the soul: Theories of self and practices of truth in Indian ethics and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Garfield, J. L. (2012). What is it like to be a bodhisattva? Moral phenomenology in Śāntideva’s Bodhicaryāvatāra. Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies, 33(1–2), 333–357.Google Scholar
  13. Garfield, J. L., Jenkins, S., & Priest, G. (2016). The Śāntideva passage: Bodhicāryāvatāra VIII.90–103. In The Cowherds (Ed.), Moonpaths: Ethics and emptiness (pp. 55–76). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Gethin, R. (2004). He who sees Dhamma sees Dhammas: Dhamma in early Buddhism. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 32(5–6), 513–542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Gold, J. (2015). Paving the great way: Vasubandhu’s unifying Buddhist philosophy. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Goodman, C. (2002). Resentment and reality: Buddhism on moral responsibility. American Philosophical Quarterly, 39(4), 359–372.Google Scholar
  17. Goodman, C. (2009a). Consequences of compassion. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Goodman, C. (2009b). Vasubandhu’s Abhidharmakośa: The critique of the soul. In W. Edelglass & J. L. Garfield (Eds.), Buddhist philosophy: Essential readings (pp. 297–308). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Gross, R. M. (1997). Toward a Buddhist environmental ethic. Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 65(2), 333–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Hamilton, S. (1996). Identity and experience: The constitution of the human being according to early Buddhism. London: Luzac Oriental.Google Scholar
  21. Harris, S. (2011). Does Anātman rationally entail altruism? On Bodhicaryāvatāra 8: 101-103. Journal of Buddhist Ethics, 18, 93–123.Google Scholar
  22. Harvey, P. (2000). An introduction to Buddhist ethics: Foundations, values and issues. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Herman, A. L. (1979). A solution to the paradox of desire in Buddhism. Philosophy East and West, 29(1), 91–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Ives, C. (1992). Zen awakening and society. Honolulu: University of Hawaiʻi Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Jenkins, S. (2016). Walking into compassion: The three Ālambana of Karuṇā. In The Cowherds (Ed.), Moonpaths: Ethics and emptiness (pp. 97–118). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Kapstein, M. T. (2001). Reason’s traces: Identity and interpretation in Indian and Tibetan Buddhist thought. Studies in Indian and Tibetan Buddhism. Boston: Wisdom Publications.Google Scholar
  27. Kellner, B., & Taber, J. (2014). Studies in Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda idealism I: The interpretation of Vasubandhu’s Viṃśikā. Asiatische Studien/Études Asiatiques, 68(3), 709–756.Google Scholar
  28. Keown, D. (1992). The nature of Buddhist ethics. New York: St. Martin’s Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. King, S. B. (2005). Being benevolence: The social ethics of engaged Buddhism. Honolulu: University of Hawaiʻi Press.Google Scholar
  30. La Vallée Poussin, L. de, & Pruden, L. M. (Trans.) (1988–1990). Abhidharmakośabhāṣyam of Vasubandhu. Berkeley: Asian Humanities Press.Google Scholar
  31. La Vallée Poussin, L. de, & Sangpo, Gelong L. (Trans.), (2012). Abhidharmakośa-Bhāṣya of Vasubandhu: The Treasury of the Abhidharma and its (Auto) Commentary. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.Google Scholar
  32. Lee, J. C. (Ed.). (2005). Abhidharmakośabhāṣya of Vasubandhu, chapter IX: Ātmavādapratiṣedha. Bibliotheca Indologica Buddhologica 11. Tokyo: Sankibo Press.Google Scholar
  33. Lowe, E. J. (2008). Personal agency: The metaphysics of mind and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. McGarrity, L. (2015). Mādhyamikas on the moral benefits of a self: Buddhists ethics and personhood. Philosophy East and West, 65(4), 1082–1118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Mele, A. R. (2003). Motivation and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Meyers, K. (2010). Freedom and self-control: Free will in South Asian Buddhism. PhD dissertation: University of Chicago.Google Scholar
  37. Meyers, K. (2014). Free persons, empty selves: Freedom and agency in light of the two truths. In M. R. Dasti & E. F. Bryant (Eds.), Free will, agency and selfhood in Indian philosophy (pp. 41–67). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Ronkin, N. (2005). Early Buddhist metaphysics: The making of a philosophical tradition. London: Routledge Curzon.Google Scholar
  39. Salvini, M. (2008). Conventions and agency in the philosophies of the Mahāyāna. PhD dissertation, School of Oriental and African Studies.Google Scholar
  40. Schechtman, M. (1996). The Constitution of Selves. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Siderits, M. (2000). The reality of altruism: Reconstructing Śāntideva. Philosophy East and West, 50(3), 412–424.Google Scholar
  42. Siderits, M. (2016). Does ‘Buddhist ethics’ exist? In The Cowherds (Ed.), Moonpaths: Ethics and emptiness (pp. 119–140). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Siderits, M. (2017). Buddhist Reductionism and the structure of Buddhist ethics. In P. Bilimoria, J. Prabhu, & R. Sharma (Eds.), Indian Ethics: Classical Traditions and Contemporary Challenges, Volume I (pp. 283–296). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  44. Steward, H. (2013). Processes, continuants and individuals. Mind, 122(487), 781–812.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Taber, J. (2011). Did Dharmakīrti think the Buddha had desires? In H. Krasser, H. Lasic, E. Franco, & B. Kellner (Eds.), Religion and logic in Buddhist philosophical analysis: Proceedings of the fourth international Dharmakīrti conference, Vienna, august 23–27, 2005 (pp. 437–448). Vienna: Verlag der Österreichischen Akademie der Wissenschaften.Google Scholar
  46. Visvader, J. (1978). The use of paradox in Uroboric philosophies. Philosophy East and West, 28(4), 455–467.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Wetlesen, J. (2002). Did Śāntideva destroy the bodhisattva path? Journal of Buddhist Ethics, 9, 34–88.Google Scholar
  48. Williams, P. M. (1981). On the Abhidharma ontology. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 9(3), 227–257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Williams, P. (1998). Altruism and reality: Studies in the philosophy of the Bodhicaryāvatāra. Richmond: Curzon Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V., part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Group in Buddhist StudiesUniversity of CaliforniaBerkeleyUSA

Personalised recommendations