Advertisement

Self-Defense, Deterrence, and the Use Objection: A Comment on Victor Tadros’s Wrongs and Crimes

  • Derk Pereboom
Original Paper
  • 91 Downloads

Abstract

In Wrongs and Crimes, Victor Tadros argues that wrongdoers acquire special duties to those they’ve wronged, and from there he generates wrongdoers’ duties to contribute to general deterrence by being punished. In support, he contends that my manipulation argument against compatibilism fails to show that causal determination is incompatible with the proposed duties wrongdoers owe to those they’ve wronged. I respond that I did not intend my manipulation argument to rule out a sense of moral responsibility that features such duties, and that I don’t believe it does. In fact, I’m willing to accept a restricted version of Tadros’s proposal, and I explain how this addition modifies the self-defense-based position on deterrence that I’ve defended in the past.

Keywords

Punishment General deterrence Special deterrence Retribution Self-defense Free will Desert Quarantine Duty Compensation 

Notes

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Dana Nelkin, Victor Tadros, and Alex Kaiserman for valuable discussion.

References

  1. Bentham, Jeremy. 1823. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  2. Boonin, David. 2008. The Problem of Punishment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Caruso, Gregg D. 2016. “Free Will Skepticism and Criminal Behavior: A Public Health Quarantine Model,” Southwest Philosophy Review 32 (1): 25–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Caruso, Gregg D. 2017. Public Health and Safety: The Social Determinants of Health and Criminal Behavior. UK: ResearchLinks Books.Google Scholar
  5. Caruso, Gregg D. 2019. “Legal Punishment and Free Will: An Epistemic Argument Against Retributivism,” Neuroethics,  https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9357-8.
  6. Farrell, Daniel M. 1985. “The Justification of General Deterrence,” The Philosophical Review 104 (3): 367–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Feinberg, Joel. 1970. “Justice and Personal Desert,” in his Doing and Deserving. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 55–94.Google Scholar
  8. Kant, Immanuel. 1790. The Metaphysics of Morals. Tr. Mary McGregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011.Google Scholar
  9. Kelly, Erin. 2009. “Criminal Justice without Retribution,” The Journal of Philosophy 106 (8): 440–462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Kleiman, Mark. 2009. When Brute Force Fails: How to Have Less Crime and Less Punishment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Marshall, S.E., and Duff, R.A. 1998. “Criminalization and Sharing Wrongs,” Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 11 (1): 7–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. McKenna, Michael. 2008. “A Hard-Line Reply to Pereboom’s Four-Case Manipulation Argument,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (1): 142–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Moore, Michael S. 1987. “The Moral Worth of Retribution,” in Punishment and rehabilitation, third edition, ed. Jeffrie G. Murphy, 94–130. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  14. Moore, Michael S. 1998. Placing Blame. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Morse, Stephen J. 2004. “Reasons, Results, and Criminal Responsibility,” University of Illinois Law Review 2004 (2): 363–444.Google Scholar
  16. Morse, Stephen J. 2013. “Common Criminal Law Compatibilism, in Neuroscience and legal responsibility, ed. Nicole A. Vincent, 29–52. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Nelkin, Dana Kay. 2013. “Desert, Fairness, and Resentment,” Philosophical Explorations 16 (2): 117–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Nelkin, Dana Kay. 2016. “Accountability and Desert,” The Journal of Ethics 20 (1–3): 173–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Nelkin, Dana Kay. 2018. “Duties, Desert, and the Justification of Punishment,” Criminal Law and Philosophy.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-018-9475-8.
  20. Otsuka, Michael. 1994. “Killing the Innocent in Self-Defense,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (1): 74–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Pereboom, Derk. 1995. “Determinism al Dente,” Noûs 29 (1): 21–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Pereboom, Derk. 2001. Living without Free Will. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Pereboom, Derk. 2014. Free Will, Agency, and Meaning in Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Pereboom. Derk. 2017. “A Defense of Free Will Skepticism,” Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (3): 617–636.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Pereboom, Derk. 2019. “Incapacitation, Reintegration, and Limited General Deterrence,” Neuroethics.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s12152-018-9382-7.
  26. Quinn, Warren. 1985. “The Right to Threaten and the Right to Punish,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (4): 327–373.Google Scholar
  27. Sartorio, Carolina. 2016. Causation and Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Scanlon, Thomas M. 2013. “Giving Desert Its Due,” Philosophical Explorations 16 (2): 101–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Schoeman, Ferdinand. 1979. “On Incapacitating the Dangerous,” American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (1): 27–35.Google Scholar
  30. Tadros, Victor. 2016. Wrongs and Crimes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Tadros, Victor. 2017. “Doing Without Desert,” Criminal Law and Philosophy 11 (3): 605–616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Vilhauer, Benjamin. 2009. “Free Will and Reasonable Doubt,” American Philosophical Quarterly 46 (2): 131–140.Google Scholar
  33. Williams, Bernard. 1976. “Moral Luck,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, v. 50, Supplementary Volume 1: 115–135; reprinted in his Moral Luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981, pp. 20–39.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyCornell UniversityIthacaUSA

Personalised recommendations