Criminal Law and Philosophy

, Volume 8, Issue 1, pp 205–215 | Cite as

Criminal Law, the Victim and Community: The Shades of ‘We’ and the Conceptual Involvement of Community in Contemporary Criminal Law Theory

Original Paper

Abstract

The article addresses the argument, put forward by Lernestedt, that the proprietor of the ‘criminal-law conflict’ is the community (or the community and the offender) and discusses his proposed theoretical model of criminal law trial. I raise questions regarding the legitimacy of such a model, focusing on four counts. Firstly, I assert that his assumptions about the state the individual and the old/new versions of criminal law theory are society-dependent. Secondly, I address some problems with the concept of community and particularly with the proposed conception of community, which seems to mostly exclude the offender. Thirdly, I question the need for (or added value of) such a proposed conceptual involvement of the community as an actor in the criminal law process and theory. Lastly, some potential problems with the idea of the victim as a mere “representative of us” are mentioned, including the possibly undesirable demands and limitations on the victim’s agency and issues of respect for the victim’s individuality.

Keywords

Criminal law Community Victim Criminalisation Offender State Conflict 

References

  1. Anttila, I. (2001). Ad Ius Criminale Humanius: Essays in criminology, criminal justice and criminal policy (edited by R. Lahti & P. Törnudd). Helsinki: Finnish Lawyers’ Association.Google Scholar
  2. Ashworth, A. (1999). Principles of criminal law (3rd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bottoms, A. (1995). The philosophy and politics of punishment and sentencing. In C. M. V. Clarkson & R. Morgan (Eds.), The politics of sentencing reform (pp. 17–50). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  4. Braithwaite, J. (1989). Crime, shame and reintegration. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Braithwaite, J. (2002). Restorative justice & responsive regulation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Christie, N. (1977). Conflicts as property. British Journal of Criminology, 17(1), 1–15.Google Scholar
  7. Christie, N. (1986). The ideal victim. In E. Fattah (Ed.), From crime policy to victim policy (pp. 17–40). New York: St. Martin’s Press.Google Scholar
  8. Cohen, S. (1979). The punitive city: Notes on the dispersal of social control. Contemporary Crises, 3, 339–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Crawford, A. (1997). The local governance of crime. In M. Wasik, Th. Gibbons & M. Redmayne (Ed.), Criminal justice (extract 1.5.7, pp. 70–77). London: Longman.Google Scholar
  10. Dignityindying (2009). A law out of step. http://www.dignityindying.org.uk/includes/spaw2/uploads/files/A%20law%20out%20of%20step.pdf. Accessed 10 June 2011.
  11. Duff, R.A. (2010). Towards a theory of criminal law? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Supplementary Vol. lxxxiv. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8349.2010.00183.x.
  12. Dworkin, R. (1977). Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Giddens, A. (2009). Sociology (6th ed.). Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  14. Jareborg, N. (1995). What kind of criminal law do we want? In A. Snare (Ed.), Beware of punishment: On the utility and futility of criminal law (pp. 17–36). Oslo: Pax Vorlag.Google Scholar
  15. Kleinig, J. (2000). The burdens of situational crime prevention: An ethical commentary. In A. von Hirsch, D. Garland, & A. Wakefield (Eds.), Ethical and social perspectives on situational crime prevention (pp. 37–58). Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
  16. Kury, H., Chouaf, S., Obergfell-Fuchs, J., & Woessner, G. (2004). The scope of sexual victimization in Germany. Journal of Interpersonal Violence, 19(5), 589–602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Lernestedt, C. (2013). Victim and society: Sharing wrongs, but in which roles? Criminal Law and Philosophy. doi:10.1007/s11572-012-9188-3.
  18. Lords Hansard (2009). 18 May 2009: Column 1273. http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/ld200809/ldhansrd/text/90518-0011.htm. Accessed 25 July 2012.
  19. Norrie, A. (1998). ‘Simulacra of morality’? Beyond the ideal/actual antinomies of criminal justice. In A. Duff (Ed.), Philosophy and the criminal law: Principle and critique (pp. 101–156). Cambridge: Cambridge Univeristy Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Peršak, N. (2007). Criminalising harmful conduct: The harm principle, its limits and continental counterparts. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  21. Peršak, N. (2012). Building justice through criminal law: Issues of criminalisation and trust. In K. Goodall, M. Malloch, & B. Munro (Eds.), Building justice in post-transition Europe? Processes of criminalisation within central and eastern European societies (pp. 43–55). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  22. Roxin, K. (2005). Strafrecht. Allgemeiner Teil, Band I, Grundlagen. Der Aufbau der Verbrechenslehre. München: Beck.Google Scholar
  23. Tham, H. (2012). The arrogance of power—The Swedish example. ESC Newsletter, 13(1), 2–3.Google Scholar
  24. Tombs, S., & Hillyard, P. (2004). Towards a political economy or harm: states, corporations and the production of inequality. In P. Hillyard, C. Pantazis, S. Tombs, & D. Gordon (Eds.), Beyond criminology: Taking harm seriously (pp. 30–55). London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
  25. Tyler, T. R. (2009). Legitimacy and criminal justice: The benefits of self-regulation. Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law, 7, 307–359.Google Scholar
  26. von Hirsch, A., Ashworth, A., & Shearing, C. (2004). Restorative justice: A ‘making amends’ model? In A. von Hirsch & A. Ashworth (Eds.), Proportionate sentencing: Exploring the principles (pp. 110–130). Oxford: Hart Publishing.Google Scholar
  27. Ward, T. (2004). State harms. In P. Hillyard, C. Pantazis, S. Tombs, & D. Gordon (Eds.), Beyond criminology: Taking harm seriously (pp. 84–101). London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
  28. Webber, F. (2004). The war on migration. In P. Hillyard, C. Pantazis, S. Tombs, & D. Gordon (Eds.), Beyond criminology: Taking harm seriously (pp. 133–156). London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
  29. Wilson, J. Q., & Kelling, G. L. (1982). Broken windows: The police and neighbourhood safety. Atlantic Monthly, 249, 28–38.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Faculty of LawUniversity of GhentGhentBelgium

Personalised recommendations