Advertisement

Criminal Law and Philosophy

, Volume 3, Issue 3, pp 301–316 | Cite as

Willfully Blind for Good Reason

  • Deborah Hellman
ORIGINAL PAPER

Abstract

Willful blindness is not an appropriate substitute for knowledge in crimes that require a mens rea of knowledge because an actor who contrives his own ignorance is only sometimes as culpable as a knowing actor. This paper begins with the assumption that the classic willfully blind actor—the drug courier—is culpable. If so, any plausible account of willful blindness must provide criteria that find this actor culpable. This paper then offers two limiting cases: a criminal defense lawyer defending a client he suspects of perjury and a pain doctor who suspects his patient may be lying about her pain. The paper argues that each of these actors is justified in cultivating ignorance about his client’s or patient’s truthfulness. If this is right, then a good theory of willful blindness must distinguish these cases. The article argues that neither Husak & Callender’s motivation-based account of willful blindness nor the recklessness account is able to do so. The paper proposes the following alternative: contrived ignorance constitutes culpable blindness when the decision to remain blind or to cultivate blindness is not itself justified. This Justification approach meshes with our intuitions about willfully blind drug couriers as well as willfully blind lawyers and doctors.

Keywords

Willful blindness Contrived ignorance Culpable blindness Justification 

References

  1. ABA Model Rules of Professional Conduct 3.3.Google Scholar
  2. Alexander, L., Ferzan, K., & Morse, S. (2009). Crime and culpability: A theory of criminal law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Applbaum, A. I. (1999). Ethics for adversaries: The morality of roles in public and professional life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Brown, W. A. (2007). Finessing the fine line between pain management and opiod addiction. Psychiatric Times, 3(2). Accessed June 2, 2009, from http://www.psychiatrictimes.com/display/article/10168/57001?pageNumber=2.
  5. Defendant’s Reply Memorandum Concerning Willful Blindness and Theory-of-Defense Instructions, United States v. Hurwitz, No. 1:03CR467 (E.D. Va. Mar. 26, 2007).Google Scholar
  6. Freedman, M. (2008). Getting honest about client perjury. Georgetown Journal of Legal Ethics, 21, 133–163.Google Scholar
  7. Government’s Memorandum Concerning Willful Blindness and Theory-of-Defense Instructions, United States v. Hurwitz, No. 1:03CR467 (E.D. Va. Mar. 26, 2007).Google Scholar
  8. Hellman, D. (2009). Prosecuting doctors for trusting patients. George Mason Law Review, 16(3), 701–745.Google Scholar
  9. Husak, D. (2008). The costs to criminal theory of supposing that intentions are irrelevant to permissibility. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 3, 51–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Husak, D., & Callender, C. (1994). Willful ignorance, knowledge, and the “equal culpability” thesis: A study of the deeper significance of the principle of legality. Wisconsin Law Review, 1994, 29–69.Google Scholar
  11. Keller, S. (2004). Friendship and belief. Philosophical Papers, 33(3), 329–351.Google Scholar
  12. Luban, D. (1988). Lawyers and justice: An ethical study. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Luban, D. (1999). Contrived ignorance. Georgetown Law Journal, 87, 957–980.Google Scholar
  14. Model Penal Cond, Sect. 2.02 (2)(b).Google Scholar
  15. Robins, I. (1990). The ostrich instruction: Deliberate ignorance as a criminal mens rea. Journal of Criminal Law & Criminology, 81(2), 191–234.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Stroud, S. (2006). Epistemic partiality in friendship. Ethics, 116, 498–524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. United States v. Hurwitz, Criminal case 1:03CR467 (2007).Google Scholar
  18. United States v. Hurwitz, 459 F.3d 463 (4th Cir. 2006).Google Scholar
  19. United States v. Jewell, 532 F.2d 697 (9th Cir. 1976).Google Scholar
  20. United States v. Katz, 445 F.3d. 1023 (8th Cir. 2006).Google Scholar
  21. United States v. McIver, 470 F.3d 550 (4th Cir. 2006).Google Scholar
  22. Walen, A. (2008). Comments on Doug Husak: The low cost of recognizing (and of ignoring) the limited relevance of intentions to permissibility. Criminal Law and Philosophy, 3, 71–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of Maryland School of LawBaltimoreUSA

Personalised recommendations