Revisiting Kantian Retributivism to Construct a Justification of Punishment

Original Paper

Abstract

The standard view of Kant’s retributivism, as well as its more recent reworking in the ‘limited’ or ‘partial’ retributivist reading are, it is argued here, inadequate accounts of Kant on punishment. In the case of the former, the view is too limited and superficial, and in the latter it is simply inaccurate as an interpretation of Kant. Instead, this paper argues that a more sophisticated and accurate rendering of Kant on punishment can be obtained by looking to his construction of the concept of justice. In so doing, not only is a superior account of Kant furnished, but also one up to the task of resolving the vexed issue of justifying legal punishment.

Keywords

Community Construction of justice Justification of punishment Kant ‘Limited’ or ‘partial’ retributivism Real negation Retributivism 

References

  1. Brown, S. M., Jr. (1962). Has Kant a philosophy of law? Philosophical Review, 71(1), 33–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Byrd, S. (1989). Kant’s theory of punishment: Deterrence in its threat, retribution in its execution. Law and Philosophy, 8, 151–200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Cooper, D. E. (1971). Hegel’s theory of punishment. In Z. A. Pelczynski (Ed.), Hegel’s political philosophy (pp. 151–167). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Ellington, J. W. (1985). The unity of Kant’s philosophy of nature. In Kant’s Philosophy of Material Nature (J. Ellington, Trans.). (pp. 137–219). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  5. Ellis, A. (1995). Critical study recent work on punishment. The Philosophical Quarterly, 45(179), 225–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Hart, H. L. A. (1968). Prolegomenon to the principles of punishment. In Punishment and Responsibility (pp. 1–27). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  7. Goldmann, L. (1971). Immanuel Kant (R. Black, Trans.). London: NLB.Google Scholar
  8. Gorner, P. (2000). The place of punishment in Kant’s rechtslehre. Kantian Review, 4, 121–130.Google Scholar
  9. Kant, I. (1929). Critique of pure reason (N. Kemp Smith, Trans.). Hampshire and London: Macmillan Press Ltd.Google Scholar
  10. Kant, I. (1985). Prolegomena to any future metaphysics. In Philosophy of material nature (pp. 1–136). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.Google Scholar
  11. Kant, I. (1991). The metaphysics of morals (M. Gregor, Trans.). Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Kant, I. (1998). Religion within the boundaries of mere reason and other writings. In K. Ameriks & D. M. Clarke (A. Wood, Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Kant, I. (1992). Attempt to introduce the concept of negative magnitudes into philosophy (1763). In D. Walford in collaboration with R. Meerbot (Eds.), Theoretical Philosophy 1755–1770 (pp. 203–241). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Kant, I. (1997). In P. Heath & J. B. Schneewind (Eds.), Lectures on ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Kant, I. (1999). Critique of practical reason. In M. J. Gregor (Ed.), The Cambridge edition of the works of Immanuel Kant practical philosophy (pp. 133–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Moggach, D. (2000). The Construction of juridical space: Kant’s analogy of relation in the metaphysics of morals. In M. D. Gedney (Ed.), The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy (pp. 201–209). Philosophy-Doc-Ctr: Bowling Green.Google Scholar
  17. Morrison, M. (1995). Space, time and reciprocity (paper presented at the Eighth International Kant Congress, Milwaukee).Google Scholar
  18. Morrison, M. (1998). Community and coexistence: Kant’s third analogy of experience. Kant-Studien, 89(3), 257–277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Murphy, J. G. (1987). Does Kant have a theory of punishment? Columbia Law Review, 87(3), 509–532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Nicholson, P. (2000). Comment on Gorner. Kantian Review, 4, 131–137.Google Scholar
  21. Potter, N. T., Jr. (1998). The principle of punishment is a categorical imperative. In J. E. Kneller (Ed.), Autonomy and community (pp. 169–190). Albany: Suny-Pr.Google Scholar
  22. Saner, H. (1973). Kant’s political thought its origins and development (E. B. Ashton, Trans.). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  23. Scheid, D. E. (1983). Kant’s retributivism. Ethics, 93(2), 262–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Schneewind, J. B. (1997). Introduction. In P. Heath & J. B. Schneewind (Eds.), Kant, I Lectures on ethics (pp. xiii-xxvii). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Shell, S. M. (1996). The embodiment of reason: Kant on spirit, generation, and community. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  26. Shell, S. M. (1997). Kant on Punishment. Kantian Review, 1, 115–135.Google Scholar
  27. Tunick, M. (1996). Is Kant a retributivist? History of Political Thought, XVII(1), 60–78.Google Scholar
  28. Wood, A. W. (1990). Hegel’s ethical thought. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Unit for the History and Philosophy of ScienceUniversity of SydneySydneyAustralia

Personalised recommendations