Criminal Law and Philosophy

, Volume 1, Issue 3, pp 233–250

Space, time and function: intersecting principles of responsibility across the terrain of criminal justice

Original Paper
  • 306 Downloads

Abstract

This paper considers the interpretive significance of the intersecting relationships between different conceptions of responsibility as they shift over space and time. The paper falls into two main sections. The first gives an account of several conceptions of responsibility: two conceptions founded in ideas of capacity; two founded in ideas of character, and one founded in the relationship between an agent and the outcome which she causes. The second main section uses this differentiated conceptual account to analyse and interpret certain aspects of the contemporary criminal law of England and Wales. In conclusion, the paper considers a number of hypotheses about what the evidence of certain shifts in the relationship between the three families of responsibility-conception can tell us about the current state and significance of criminal law among other systems of social governance.

Keywords

Crime Responsibility Capacity Character Outcome 

References

  1. Arenella, P. (1990). Character, choice and moral agency: The relevance of character to our moral culpability judgments. Social Philosophy & Policy, 7, 59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Ashworth, A., & Blake, M. (1996). The presumption of innocence in English criminal law. Criminal Law Review 306.Google Scholar
  3. Bayles, M. (1982). Character, purpose and criminal responsibility. Law and Philosophy, 1, 5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Dubber, M. (2005). The police power. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Duff, R. A. (1986). Trials and punishments. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Duff, R. A. (1993). Choice, character and criminal liability. Law and Philosophy, 12, 345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Duff, R. A. (2002). Virtue, vice and criminal liability: Do we want an Aristotelian criminal law?. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 147.Google Scholar
  8. Eigen, J. P. (1999). Lesion of the will: Medical resolve and criminal responsibility in Victorian insanity trials. Law and Society Review, 33, 425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Farmer, L. (1996). Criminal law, tradition and legal order. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Field, S., & Roberts, P. (2002). Racism and police investigations. Legal Studies, 22, 493.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fletcher, G. (1978). Rethinking criminal law. Boston and Toronto: Little, Brown & Co.Google Scholar
  12. Gardner, J. (1998). The gist of excuses. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 1, 575.Google Scholar
  13. Gatens, M., & Lloyd, G. (1999). Collective imaginings. London: Routledge, Chapters 3 and 6.Google Scholar
  14. Hall, J. A. (1952). Theft, law and society. 2nd ed. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
  15. Hart, H. L. A. (1968). Punishment and responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  16. Hillyard P., Pantazis C., Tombs S., & Gordon D. (Eds.), (2004). Beyond criminology: Taking harm seriously. London: Pluto Press.Google Scholar
  17. Home Office (2000) Statistics on race and the criminal justice system. London: Home Office.Google Scholar
  18. Honoré, T. (1988) Responsibility and luck: The moral basis of strict liability. Law Quarterly Review, 104, 530, reprinted in Tony Honor?, Responsibility and fault. Hart Publishing, 1999, p.14.Google Scholar
  19. Horder, J. (1993). Criminal culpability: The possibility of a general theory. Law and Philosophy, 12, 193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Horder, J. (1996). Determinism, liberalism and criminal law. Current Legal Problems, 49, 159.Google Scholar
  21. Huigens, K. (1995). Virtue and inculpation. Harvard Law Review, 108, 1423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kahan, D. M., & Nussbaum, M. C. (1996). Two conceptions of emotion in criminal law. Columbia Law Review, 96, 269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Katz, L. (2002). Villainy and felony: A problem concerning criminalization. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 451.Google Scholar
  24. Kinsey, R., Lea, J., & Young, J. (1986). Losing the fight against crime. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  25. Lacey, N. (1988). State punishment. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  26. Lacey, N. (1991). Reconstructing the criminal. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Lacey, N. (2000). Partial excuses to homicide. In A. Ashworth & B. Mitchell (Eds.), Rethinking English homicide law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  28. Lacey, N. (forthcoming). Character, capacity and outcome: Towards a framework for assessing the shifting pattern of criminal responsibility in modern English law. In M. Dubber & L. Farmer (Eds.), Modern histories of crime and punishment. Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Lacey, N. (2001a). In search of the responsible subject: History, philosophy and criminal law theory. Modern Law Review, 64, 350–371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Lacey, N. (2001b). Responsibility and modernity in criminal law. Journal of Political Philosophy, 9, 249–277.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Lacey, N. (2004). Criminalisation as regulation: The role of criminal law. In C. Parker, et al. (Eds.), Regulating law (pp. 144–167). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Lacey, N. (2006). Historicising contrasts in tolerance. In T. Newburn & P. Rock (Eds.), The politics of crime control (pp. 197–226). Oxford University Press. .Google Scholar
  33. Lacey, N., Wells, C., & Quick, O. (2003). Reconstructing criminal law, 3rd ed. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Lustgarten, L. (2002). The future of stop and search. Criminal Law Review, 603.Google Scholar
  35. MacPherson Report (1999). The Stephen Lawrence inquiry. London: HMSO, Cm 4262.Google Scholar
  36. Michaels, A. C. (1998). Acceptance: The missing mental state. S. California Law Review, 71, 953.Google Scholar
  37. Norrie, A. (2001). Crime, reason and history, 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Nourse, V. F. (2002). Hearts and minds: Understanding the new culpability. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 361–388.Google Scholar
  39. Phillips, C., & Bowling, B. (2002). Racism, ethnicity, crime and criminal justice. In R. M. Maguire, & R. Reiner (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of criminology, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  40. Pillsbury, S. H. (2002). A problem in emotive due process: California’s Three Strikes Law. Buffalo Criminal Law Review, 6, 483.Google Scholar
  41. Ramsay, P. (2004). What is anti-social behaviour? Criminal Law Review, 908–925.Google Scholar
  42. Redmayne, M. (2002). The relevance of bad character. Cambridge Law Journal, 61, 684–714.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Schoeman, F. (Ed.) (1987). Responsibility, character and the emotions. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Smith, R. (1981). Trial by medicine. Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Smith, K. J. M. (1998). Lawyers, legislators and theorists. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  46. Strawson, P. F. (1982). Freedom and resentment. In G. Watson (Ed.), Free will. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Tadros, V. (2005). Criminal responsibility. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  48. Teubner, G. (1993). Law as an autopoietic system. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  49. Whitman, J. Q. (2003). Harsh justice. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Williams, B. (1981). Persons, character and morality. In Moral luck (p. 1). Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Williams, G. (1983). Textbook of criminal law. 2nd ed. London: Sweet and Maxwell.Google Scholar
  52. Yankah, E. N. (2004). Good guys and bad guys: Punishing character, equality and the irrelevance of moral character to criminal punishment. Cardozo Law Review, 24, 1019–1067.Google Scholar
  53. Young, J. (1999). The exclusive society. Sage.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Law DepartmentLondon School of EconomicsLondonUK

Personalised recommendations