Philosophia

, Volume 35, Issue 2, pp 181–196 | Cite as

BonJour’s Abductivist Reply to Skepticism

Article

Abstract

The abductivist reply to skepticism is the view that commonsense explanations of the patterns and regularities that appear in our sensory experiences should be rationally preferred to skeptical explanations of those same patterns and regularities on the basis of explanatory considerations. In this article I critically examine Laurence BonJour’s rationalist version of the abductivist position. After explaining why BonJour’s account is more defensible than other versions of the view, I argue that the notion of probability he relies upon is deeply problematic, that he incorporates an implausible double-standard concerning a priori and a posteriori justification, and that his view is vulnerable to skepticism about the a priori. I suggest that some of these problems are due to idiosyncratic commitments BonJour makes and that abductivists would be better off without them. I conclude with some suggestions about how to improve BonJour’s abductivist response to skepticism.

Keywords

Skepticism Abductivism Rationalism Inference to the best explanation BonJour 

References

  1. Alston, W. (1999). Perceptual knowledge. In J. Greco & E. Sosa (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to epistemology (pp. 223–242). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  2. Ayer, A. J. (1956). The problem of knowledge. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  3. Beebe, J. R. (forthcoming a). A priori skepticism. Google Scholar
  4. Beebe, J. R. (forthcoming b). Can rationalist abductivism solve the problem of induction?Google Scholar
  5. Beebe, J. R. (forthcoming c). The abductivist reply to skepticism. Google Scholar
  6. Bennett, J. (1971). Locke, Berkeley, Hume: Central themes. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  7. BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  8. BonJour, L. (1998). In defense of pure reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. BonJour, L. (1999). Foundationalism and the external world. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives, vol 13 (pp. 229–249). Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  10. BonJour, L. (2002). Epistemology: Classic problems and contemporary responses. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  11. BonJour, L. (2003). A version of internalist founationalism. In BonJour & Sosa (2003).Google Scholar
  12. BonJour, L., & Sosa, E. (2003). Epistemic justification: Internalism vs. externalism, foundations vs. virtues. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. Broad, C. D. (1925). The mind and its place in nature. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  14. Cornman, J. W. (1980). Skepticism, justification, and explanation. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  15. Descartes, R. (1984). The philosophical writings of Descartes. Trans. by John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. vols 1 & 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  17. Fumerton, R. (2005). The challenge of refuting skepticism. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 85–97). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  18. Goldman, A. (1988). Empirical knowledge. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  19. Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Jackson, F. (1977). Perception: A representative theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Locke, J. (1690/1975). An essay concerning human understanding. In P. H. Nidditch (Ed.). Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  22. Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement and justification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Mackie, J. L. (1976). Problems from Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Moser, P. K. (1989). Knowledge and evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Psillos, S. (1996). On van Fraassen’s critique of abductive reasoning. Philosophical Quarterly, 46, 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Ramsey, F. P. (1926). Truth and probability (pp. 156–198). Reprinted in Ramsey (1931).Google Scholar
  27. Ramsey, F. P. 1931. The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays. In R. B. Braithwaite (Ed.). New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co.Google Scholar
  28. Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Russell, B. (1927). The analysis of matter. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  30. Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. London: G. Allen.Google Scholar
  31. Slote, M. A. (1970). Reason and scepticism. London: G. Allen.Google Scholar
  32. van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  33. Vogel, J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 87, 658–666.Google Scholar
  34. Vogel, J. (2005). The refutation of skepticism. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 72–84). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  35. Wrenn, C. B. (2006). Inter-world probability and the problem of induction. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 87, 387–402.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophySUNY–BuffaloBuffaloUSA

Personalised recommendations