Advertisement

Topoi

, Volume 36, Issue 3, pp 393–407 | Cite as

Sensorimotor Theory and Enactivism

  • Jan DegenaarEmail author
  • J. Kevin O’Regan
Article

Abstract

The sensorimotor theory of perceptual consciousness offers a form of enactivism in that it stresses patterns of interaction instead of any alleged internal representations of the environment. But how does it relate to forms of enactivism stressing the continuity between life and mind (and more particularly autopoiesis, autonomy, and valence)? We shall distinguish sensorimotor enactivism, which stresses perceptual capacities themselves, from autopoietic enactivism, which claims an essential connection between experience and autopoietic processes or associated background capacities. We show how autopoiesis, autonomous agency, and affective dimensions of experience may fit into sensorimotor enactivism, and we identify differences between this interpretation and autopoietic enactivism. By taking artificial consciousness as a case in point, we further sharpen the distinction between sensorimotor enactivism and autopoietic enactivism. We argue that sensorimotor enactivism forms a strong default position for an enactive account of perceptual consciousness.

Keywords

Consciousness Sensorimotor theory Enactivism Autopoiesis Artificial consciousness 

Notes

Acknowledgments

We thank Sanneke de Haan, Erik Myin, David Silverman and the audience at the 2014 AISB conference at Goldsmiths, University of London for helpful discussions and critique on an earlier version of this paper. We further thank our anonymous reviewers for their excellent comments and suggestions. The work was supported by ERC advanced Grant 323674 “FEEL” of J. Kevin O’Regan.

References

  1. Block N (2007) Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behav Brain Sci 30(5):481–548Google Scholar
  2. Bower M, Gallagher S (2013) Bodily affects as prenoetic elements in enactive perception. Phenomenol Mind 4(1):78–93Google Scholar
  3. Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  4. Clark A (2008) Pressing the flesh: a tension in the study of the embodied, embedded mind? Phil Phenomenol Res 76(1):37–59Google Scholar
  5. Cooke E, Myin E (2011) Is trilled smell possible? How the structure of olfaction determines the phenomenology of smell. J Conscious Stud 18(11–12):59–95Google Scholar
  6. Davidson D (1987) Knowing one’s own mind. Proc Address Am Philos Assoc 60(3):441–458Google Scholar
  7. Degenaar J, O’Regan JK (2015) Sensorimotor theory of consciousness. Scholarpedia 10(5):4952CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness explained. Little, Brown and Company, BostonGoogle Scholar
  9. Di Paolo EA (2003) Organismically-inspired robotics: homeostatic adaptation and teleology beyond the closed sensorimotor loop. In: Murase K, Asakura T (eds) Dynamical systems approaches to embodiment and sociality. Advanced Knowledge International, Adelaide, pp 19–42Google Scholar
  10. Di Paolo EA (2005) Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 4(4):429–452CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Di Paolo EA (2009) Extended life. Topoi 28(1):9–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Di Paolo EA, Iizuka H (2008) How (not) to model autonomous behaviour. BioSystems 91(2):409–423CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dreyfus H, Kelly SD (2007) Heterophenomenology: heavy-handed sleight-of-hand. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 6(1–2):45–55CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hurley SL (1998) Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  15. Hurley SL (2001) Perception and action: alternative views. Synthese 129(1):3–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hutto D (2005) Knowing what? Radical versus conservative enactivism. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 4(4):389–405Google Scholar
  17. Jonas H (1966) The phenomenon of life: toward a philosophical biology. Northwestern University Press, EvanstonGoogle Scholar
  18. Kiverstein J (2007) Could a robot have a subjective point of view? J Conscious Stud 14(7):127–139Google Scholar
  19. Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. Springer, BerlinCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Maye A, Engel AK (2012) Time scales of sensorimotor contingencies. In: Zhang H, Hussain A, Liu D, Wang Z (eds) Advances in brain inspired cognitive systems. Springer, Berlin, pp 240–249CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Noë A (2004) Action in perception. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  22. O’Regan JK (2011) Why red doesn’t sound like a bell: understanding the feel of consciousness. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. O’Regan JK, Noë A (2001) A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behav Brain Sci 24(5):883–917Google Scholar
  24. Philipona DL, O’Regan J (2006) Color naming, unique hues, and hue cancellation predicted from singularities in reflection properties. Vis Neurosci 23(3–4):331–339CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Rietveld E (2008) Situated normativity: the normative aspect of embodied cognition in unreflective action. Mind 117(468):973–1001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Ryle G (1949) The concept of mind. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  27. Simons DJ, Chabris CF (1999) Gorillas in our midst: sustained inattentional blindness for dynamic events. Perception 28(9):1059–1074CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Sloman A (2010) Phenomenal and access consciousness and the “hard” problem: a view from the designer stance. Int J Machine Conscious 2(01):117–169CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Stapleton M (2013) Steps to a “properly embodied” cognitive science. Cogn Syst Res 22–23:1–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Sytsma J, Machery E (2010) Two conceptions of subjective experience. Philos Stud 151(2):299–327CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Thompson E (2005) Sensorimotor subjectivity and the enactive approach to experience. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 4(4):407–427CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Thompson E (2007) Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  33. Varela FJ (1979) Principles of biological autonomy. Elsevier, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  34. Varela FJ, Thompson E, Rosch E (1991) The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  35. Withagen R, de Poel HJ, Araújo D, Pepping G-J (2012) Affordances can invite behavior: reconsidering the relationship between affordances and agency. New Ideas Psychol 30(2):250–258CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Wittgenstein L (1953) Philosophical investigations. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  37. Ziemke T (2007) The embodied self: theories, hunches and robot models. J Conscious Stud 14(7):167–179Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Laboratoire Psychologie de la PerceptionUniversité Paris DescartesParisFrance
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of AntwerpAntwerpBelgium

Personalised recommendations