Advertisement

Topoi

, Volume 35, Issue 2, pp 395–402 | Cite as

Intellectual Humility, Confidence, and Argumentation

  • Ian James Kidd
Article

Abstract

In this paper, I explore the relationship of virtue, argumentation, and philosophical conduct by considering the role of the specific virtue of intellectual humility in the practice of philosophical argumentation. I have three aims: first, to sketch an account of this virtue; second, to argue that it can be cultivated by engaging in argumentation with others; and third, to problematize this claim by drawing upon recent data from social psychology. My claim is that philosophical argumentation can be conducive to the cultivation of virtues, including humility, but only if it is conceived and practiced in appropriately ‘edifying’ ways.

Keywords

Argumentation Confidence Humility Virtue Bias Social psychology 

References

  1. Aberdein A (2010) Virtue in argument. Argumentation 24(2):165–179CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Aberdein A (2014) Virtues and arguments: a bibliography. https://www.academia.edu/5620761/Virtues_and_Arguments_A_Bibliography
  3. Ahlstrom-Vij K (2013) Epistemic paternalism: a defence. Palgrave Macmillan, BasingstokeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Aristotle (1997) Topics (trans: Smith R). Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  5. Baehr J (2011) The inquiring mind: on intellectual virtues and virtue epistemology. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bondy P (2010) Argumentative injustice. Informal Log 30(3):263–278Google Scholar
  7. Cohen D (1995) Argument is war… and war is hell: philosophy, education, and metaphors for argumentation. Informal Log 17(2):177–188Google Scholar
  8. Cohen D (2004) Arguments and metaphors in philosophy. University Press of America, LanhamGoogle Scholar
  9. Cohen D (2005) Arguments that backfire. In: Hitchcock D, Farr D (eds) The uses of argument. OSSA, Hamilton, pp 58–65Google Scholar
  10. Cohen D (2007) Virtue epistemology and argumentation theory. In: Hansen HV et al (eds) Dissensus and the search for common ground. OSSA, Windsor, pp 1–9Google Scholar
  11. Cohen D (2009) Keeping an open mind and having a sense of proportion as virtues in argumentation. Cogency 1(2):49–64Google Scholar
  12. Confucius (2006) The essential Analects: selected passages with traditional commentary (trans: Slingerland E). Hackett, IndianapolisGoogle Scholar
  13. Correia V (2012) The ethics of argumentation. Informal Log 32:219–238Google Scholar
  14. Davids TWR (1890) The questions of king Milinda. Pali Text Society, LondonGoogle Scholar
  15. de Beauvoir S (1963) Memoirs of a dutiful daughter. Penguin, HarmondsworthGoogle Scholar
  16. de Montaigne M (1991) Essays (ed & trans: Screech MA). Penguin, LondonGoogle Scholar
  17. Doris J (2002) Lack of character: personality and moral behaviour. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Dutilh Novaes C (2014) Virtuous adversariality as a model for philosophical inquiry. Talk given at the Edinburgh Women in Philosophy Spring Workshop. Philosophical Methodologies, University of Edinburgh, 16 MayGoogle Scholar
  19. Fricker M (2007) Epistemic injustice: power and the ethics of knowing. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gilovich T, Griffin D, Kahneman D (eds) (2002) Heuristics and biases: the psychology of intuitive judgement. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  21. Govier T (1999) The philosophy of argument. Vale, Newport NewsGoogle Scholar
  22. Greenwald AG, Banaji MR (1995) Implicit social cognition: attitudes, self-esteem, and stereotypes. Psychol Rev 102:4–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hadot P (1995) Philosophy as a way of life: spiritual exercises from Socrates to Foucault. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  24. Hadot P (2004) What is philosophy? (trans: Chase M). Harvard University Press, HarvardGoogle Scholar
  25. Hume D (2000) A treatise of human nature. In: DF Norton, MJ Norton (eds). Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  26. Jenkins F, Hutchison K (eds) (2012) Women in philosophy: What needs to change? Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  27. Jones WE (2012) Higher education, academic communities, and the intellectual virtues. Educ Theory 62(6):695–711CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Kahneman D, Slovic P, Tversky A (eds) (1982) Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  29. Kidd IJ (forthcoming) Educating for epistemic humility. In: Baehr J (ed) Intellectual virtues and education: essays in applied virtue epistemology. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  30. Lakoff G, Johnson M (2003) Metaphors we live by. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Le Doeuff M (2006) Hipparchia’s choice: an essay concerning women, philosophy, etc. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  32. Lee CJ, Schunn CD (2011) Social biases and solutions for procedural objectivity. Hypatia 26:352–373CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Lloyd G (1993) The man of reason: ‘Male’ and ‘Female’ in western philosophy, 2nd edn. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  34. Nickerson RS (1998) Confirmation bias: a ubiquitous phenomenon in many guises. Rev Gen Psychol 2(2):175–220CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Oakeshott M (2004) What is history? and other essays. In: O’Sullivan L (ed) Imprint Academic, ExeterGoogle Scholar
  36. Pardue ST (2013) The mind of Christ: humility and the intellect in early Christian theology. Bloomsbury, LondonGoogle Scholar
  37. Plato (1986) Charmides (trans: West TG, West GS). Hackett, IndianapolisGoogle Scholar
  38. Riggs W (2010) Open-mindedness. Metaphilosophy 41(1–2):172–188CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Roberts RC, Wood WJ (2007) Intellectual virtues: an essay in regulative epistemology. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Rushing S (2013) What is Confucian humility? In: Angle S, Slote M (eds) Virtue ethics and confucianism. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  41. Saul J (2012) Implicit bias, stereotype threat, and women in philosophy. In: Jenkins F, Hutchison K (eds) Women in philosophy: What needs to change? Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  42. Stevens K (2015) The virtuous arguer: one person, four roles, Topoi, forthcomingGoogle Scholar
  43. Taylor C (2007) A secular age. Harvard University Press, HarvardGoogle Scholar
  44. Tiberius V, Walker JD (1998) Arrogance. Am Philos Q 35(4):379–390Google Scholar
  45. Valian V (1999) Why so slow? Advancement of women. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  46. Williams B (2009) Philosophy as a humanistic discipline (selected, edited, and with an introduction by Moore AW). Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  47. Zagzebski L (1996) Virtues of the mind: an inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Zagzebski L (2012) Epistemic authority: a theory of trust, authority, and autonomy in belief. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyDurham UniversityDurhamUK

Personalised recommendations