Advertisement

Topoi

, Volume 35, Issue 2, pp 359–366 | Cite as

Thick, Thin, and Becoming a Virtuous Arguer

  • Juli K. Thorson
Article

Abstract

A virtue account is focused on the character of those who argue. It is frequently assumed, however, that virtues are not action guiding, since they describe how to be and so fail to give us specific actions to take in a sticky situation. In terms of argumentation, we might say that being a charitable arguer is virtuous, but knowing so provides no details about how to argue successfully. To close this gap, I develop a parallel with the thick-thin distinction from ethics and use Hursthouse’s notion of “v-rules”. I also draw heavily from the work in argumentation by Daniel Cohen to develop Wayne Brockriede’s notion of arguing lovingly. But “argue lovingly” has a delicious ambiguity. For Brockriede it describes how we engage with others arguers. It can also mean, however, a loving attachment to knowledge, understanding, and truth. Applying the thick-thin distinction to argumentation in general and loving argumentation in particular shows that a virtue theoretic approach to argumentation is valuable for two reasons: it can provide one articulation of what it means to be a virtuous arguer and provide some insights into how to become one.

Keywords

Virtuous argumentation Virtuous community Thick-thin V-rules Articulacy Deliberative groups Argue lovingly Hursthouse Annas Brockriede 

References

  1. Aikin S, Clanton JC (2010) Developing group-deliberative virtues. J Appl Philos 27:409–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Annas J (2011) Practical expertise. In: Bengson J, Moffett M (eds) Knowing How. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 101–112Google Scholar
  3. Annas J (2014) Virtue rules and thick concepts. Conference presentation, Virtue and its developments, University of Notre Dame, 19–22 MayGoogle Scholar
  4. Brockriede W (1972) Arguers as lovers. Philos Rhetor 5:1–11Google Scholar
  5. Cohen DH (2001) Evaluating arguments and making meta-arguments. Informal Logic 21:73–84Google Scholar
  6. Cohen DH (2009) Keeping an open mind and having a sense of proportion as virtues in argumentation. Cogency 1:49–64Google Scholar
  7. Hursthouse R (1999) On virtue ethics. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  8. Kirchin S (2013a) Thick concepts. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Kirchin S (2013b) Introduction: thick and thin concepts. In: Kirchin S (ed) Thick concepts. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–19CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Kirchin S (2013c) Thick concepts and thick descriptions. In: Kirchin S (ed) Thick concepts. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 60–77CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Noddings N (1984) Caring: a feminist approach to ethics and moral education. University of California Press, OaklandGoogle Scholar
  12. Norlock KJ (2013) Receptivity as a virtue of (practitioners of) argumentation. In: Mohammed D, Lewinski M (eds) Virtues of argumentation: proceedings of the 10th international conference of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation (OSSA), 1–8. http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA10/papersandcommentaries/121/ Accessed June 12, 2014
  13. Roberts D (2013) It’s evaluation, only thicker. In: Kirchin S (ed) Thick concepts. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 87–114Google Scholar
  14. Snow NE (2010) Virtue as social intelligence: an empirically grounded theory. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  15. Swanton C (2003) Virtue ethics: a pluralistic view. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  16. Zagzebski LT (2006) The admirable life and the desirable life. In: Chappell T (ed) Values and virtues, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 53–66Google Scholar
  17. Zagzebski LT (2010) Exemplarist virtue theory. Metaphilosophy 41:41–57CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Ball State UniversityMuncieUSA

Personalised recommendations