Abstract
The straw man fallacy consists in inappropriately constructing or selecting weak (or comparatively weaker) versions of the opposition’s arguments. We will survey the three forms of straw men recognized in the literature, the straw, weak, and hollow man. We will then make the case that there are examples of inappropriately reconstructing stronger versions of the opposition’s arguments. Such cases we will call iron man fallacies. The difference between appropriate and inappropriate iron manning clarifies the limits of the virtue of open-mindedness.
Keywords
Iron man fallacy Open-mindedness Straw man fallacy Weak man fallacyReferences
- Aikin S (2008) Holding one’s own. Argumentation 22:571–584CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Aikin S, Casey J (2011) Straw men, weak men, and hollow men. Argumentation 25:87–105CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Aikin S, Clanton C (2010) Developing deliberative virtues. J Appl Philos 27(4):409–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Anderson A, Brossard D, Scheufele DA, Xenos MA, Ladwig P (2013) The “nasty effect:” online incivility and risk perceptions of emerging technologies. J Comput-Mediat Commun 19(3):373–387CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Baronett S (2008) Logic. OxfordGoogle Scholar
- Bizer GY, Kozak SM, Holterman LA (2009) The persuasiveness of the straw man rhetorical technique. Soc Influ 4:216–230CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- CBS News, 60 Minutes (2012) Interview with Eric Cantor. http://www.cbsnews.com/8301-18560_162-57348499/the-majority-leader-rep-eric-cantor/?tag=contentMain;cbsCarousel
- De Bruin B (2013) Epistemic virtues in business. J Bus Ethics 113(4):583–595CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ferkany M, Whyte KP (2011) The importance of participatory virtues in the future of environmental education. J Agric Environ Ethics 25(3):419–434CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Govier T (1997) A practical study of argument, 4e. Wadsworth, Belmont, CAGoogle Scholar
- Hare W (2003) Is it good to be open-minded? Int J Appl Philos 17(1):3–87Google Scholar
- Kitcher P (1982) Abusing science. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
- Lewinksi M (2011) Towards a critique-friendly approach to straw man fallacy evaluation. Argumentation 25:469–497CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lewiński M, Oswald S (2013) When and how do we deal with straw men? A normative and cognitive pragmatic account. J Pragmat 59:164–177Google Scholar
- Ribeiro B (2008) How often do we (philosophy professors) commit the straw man fallacy? Teach Philos 31:27–38CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Scott K (2014) The political value of humility. Acta Polit 49:217–233CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Siegel H (1995) What price inclusion? Teach Coll Rec 97:6–31Google Scholar
- Talisse R, Aikin S (2008) Two forms of the straw man. Argumentation 20:345–352Google Scholar
- Talisse R, Raley Y (2008) Getting duped: how the media messes with your mind. Sci Am Mind 2008(Feb/March):16–17Google Scholar
- Tindale C (2007) Fallacies and argument appraisal. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Van Laar JA (2008) Room for maneuver when raising critical doubt. Philos Rhetor 41:195–211CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Walton D (1998) Ad hominem arguments. University of Alabama Press, BirminghamGoogle Scholar
- Walton D, Krabbe E (1995) Commitment in dialogue. State University of New York Press, AlbanyGoogle Scholar
- Walton D, Macagno F (2010) Wrenching from context: the manipulation of commitments. Argumentation 24:283–317CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Walton D, Reed C, Macagno F (2008) Argumentation schemes. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Copyright information
© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2015