Axiomatizations of the proportional Shapley value Manfred Besner Article First Online: 31 January 2019
Abstract We present new axiomatic characterizations of the proportional Shapley value, a weighted TU-value with the worths of the singletons as weights. The presented characterizations are proportional counterparts to the famous characterizations of the Shapley value by Shapley (Contributions to the theory of games, vol. 2. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 307–317, 1953b ) and Young (Cost allocation: methods, principles, applications. North Holland Publishing Co, 1985a ). We introduce two new axioms, called proportionality and player splitting, respectively. Each of them makes a main difference between the proportional Shapley value and the Shapley value. If the stand-alone worths are plausible weights, the proportional Shapley value is a convincing alternative to the Shapley value, for example in cost allocation. Especially, the player splitting property, which states that players’ payoffs do not change if another player splits into two new players who have the same impact to the game as the original player, justifies the use of the proportional Shapley value in many economic situations.
Keywords Cost allocation Dividends Proportional Shapley value (Weighted) Shapley value Proportionality Player splitting This is a preview of subscription content,
log in to check access.
Notes Acknowledgements We would like to thank André Casajus, Winfried Hochstättler, Jörg Homberger, Frank Huettner, Hans Peters, and especially an anonymous referee for their helpful comments and suggestions.
Publisher's Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Appendix Additional lemmas and a remark, used in the proofs Proofs Proof of Lemma 1 Let
\(i,j \in N\) and
\(v \in \mathcal {G}^N\) . If
\(S= \emptyset \) , we have
\(v(S\cup \{k\})=v(S)+v(\{k\})\) . By induction on the size
\(s:=|S|\) of all coalitions
\(S \subseteq N\backslash \{i,j\},\,S \ne \emptyset ,\) we show that
$$\begin{aligned} v(S\cup \{k\})=v(S)+v(\{k\})\quad \Leftrightarrow \quad \varDelta _v(S \cup \{k\})=0. \end{aligned}$$
Initialization: Let
\(s=1\) . For
\(k \in \{i,j\}\) we have the following:
$$\begin{aligned}{}\begin{array}[b]{crcl} &{}v(S\cup \{k\}) &{}=&{}v(S)+v(\{k\})\\ \underset{(1)}{\Leftrightarrow }&{} \varDelta _v(S\cup \{k\})+\varDelta _v(S)+\varDelta _v(\{k\})&{}=&{}\varDelta _v(S)+\varDelta _v(\{k\})\\ \Leftrightarrow &{}\varDelta _v(S\cup \{k\})&{}=&{}0. \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
Induction step: Assume that equivalence and equality in the first and last line of the system above hold for all coalitions
\(S'\) with
\(s'\ge 1\) (
IH ), and let
\(s=s'+1\) and
\(k \in \{i,j\}\) . We get the following:
$$\begin{aligned}\begin{array}{crcl} &{}v(S\cup \{k\}) &{}=&{}v(S)+v(\{k\})\\ \underset{(1)}{\Leftrightarrow }&{} \varDelta _v(S\cup \{k\})+\displaystyle {\sum _{R\subsetneq (S\cup \{k\})}\varDelta _v(R)}&{}=&{}\displaystyle {\sum _{R\subseteq S}\varDelta _v(R)}+\varDelta _v(\{k\})\\ \underset{(IH)}{\Leftrightarrow }&{}\varDelta _v(S\cup \{k\})+\varDelta _v(\{k\})+\displaystyle {\sum _{R\subseteq S}\varDelta _v(R)}&{}=&{}\displaystyle {\sum _{R\subseteq S}\varDelta _v(R)}+\varDelta _v(\{k\})\\ \Leftrightarrow &{}\varDelta _v(S\cup \{k\})&{}=&{}0. \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
Thus, the equivalence is shown.
\(\square \) Proof of Theorem 1 I. Existence: By Béal et al. (2018 ), \({\text {Sh}}^p\) satisfies E and D .
\(\bullet \) P : Let
\(v \in \mathcal {G}_{0}^N\) and
\(i,j \in N\) , such that
i and
j are weakly dependent in
v . We have the following:
$$\begin{aligned}{}\begin{array}[b]{rcl} {\text {Sh}}^{p}_i(v)&{} = &{}\displaystyle {\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{k \in S}v(\{k\})}\varDelta _v(S)}\underset{Lem. 1}{=}v(\{i\})+ \sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {\{i,j\} \subseteq S} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{k \in S}v(\{k\})}\varDelta _v(S)\\ &{}=&{}\displaystyle {\frac{v(\{i\})}{v(\{j\})}v(\{j\})+\frac{v(\{i\})}{v(\{j\})} \sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {\{i,j\} \subseteq S} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{j\})}{\sum _{k \in S}v(\{k\})}\varDelta _v(S)}\\ &{}\underset{Lem.1}{=}&{}\displaystyle {\frac{v(\{i\})}{v(\{j\})} \sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni j} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{j\})}{\sum _{k \in S}v(\{k\})}\varDelta _v(S)}=\frac{v(\{i\})}{v(\{j\})}{\text {Sh}}^{p}_j(v). \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
\(\bullet \) WA : Let
\(v,w \in \mathcal {G}_{0}^N\) with
\(w(\{i\})=c\cdot v(\{i\})\) for all
\(i \in N,\, c>0\) . We have the following:
$$\begin{aligned}{}\begin{array}[b]{rcl} {\text {Sh}}_i^p(v)+ {\text {Sh}}_i^p(w)&{} \underset{(3)}{=}&{} \displaystyle {\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}v(\{j\})}\varDelta _v(S)+\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ w(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}w(\{j\})}\varDelta _w(S)} \\ &{}=&{}\displaystyle {\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}v(\{j\})}\varDelta _v(S)+\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ c\cdot v(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}c\cdot v(\{j\})}\varDelta _w(S)} \\ &{}=&{}\displaystyle {\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}v(\{j\})}\big [\varDelta _v(S)+\varDelta _w(S)\big ]} \\ &{}=&{} \displaystyle {\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ (1+c)v(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}(1+c)v(\{j\})}\big [\varDelta _v(S)+\varDelta _w(S)\big ]} \\ &{}=&{}\displaystyle {\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})+w(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}\big [v(\{j\})+w(\{j\})\big ]}\varDelta _{v+w}(S)}\\[1ex] &{}=&{} {\text {Sh}}_i^p(v+w). \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
II. Uniqueness: Let
\(N\in \mathcal {N}, \,n:=|N|\) ,
\(v \in \mathcal {G}^{N}_{0},\) and
\(\varphi \) a TU-value which satisfies all axioms of Theorem
1 . To prove uniqueness, we will show that
\(\varphi \) equals
\({\text {Sh}}^p\) .
For \(n=1\) , \(\varphi \) equals \({\text {Sh}}^p\) by E .
Let now
\(n\ge 2\) . For each coalition
\(S \subseteq N,\,S\ne \emptyset ,\) we define, corresponding to Remark
4 , a TU-game
\(v_S \in \mathcal {G}^{N}_{0}\) through a vector
\(\overrightarrow{v_S}\in \mathbb {R}^{2^N-1}\) by assigning the coordinates of the related vector
\(\overrightarrow{\varDelta _{v_S}}\in \mathbb {R}^{2^N-1}\) in the entry of a coalition
\(R \subseteq N,\, R \ne \emptyset ,\) the dividend:
$$\begin{aligned} \varDelta _{v_S}(R):= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}\dfrac{v(\{j\})}{2^n-1}, \text { if } R=\{j\} \text { for all } j\in N, \\ \varDelta _{v}(S), \text { if } R=S, \,|S| \ge 2,\\ 0, \,\text {otherwise.} \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
Thus, each vector
\(\overrightarrow{v_S}\in \mathbb {R}^{2^N-1}\) gets in the coordinates of coalitions
\(R\subseteq N,\,R \ne \emptyset ,\) the entry:
$$\begin{aligned} v_S(R)= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \varDelta _v(S)+\sum \nolimits _{j\in R}\dfrac{v(\{j\})}{2^n-1}, \text { if } R\supseteq S,\,|S| \ge 2,\\ \sum \nolimits _{j \in R}\dfrac{v(\{j\})}{2^n-1},\,\text {otherwise.} \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
(5)
We have
\(\displaystyle {\overrightarrow{\varDelta _{v}}=\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S \subseteq N, \\ S\ne \emptyset \; \end{array}}\overrightarrow{\varDelta _{v_S}}}\) , and so, by Remark
4 ,
\(\displaystyle {v=\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S \subseteq N, \\ S\ne \emptyset \; \end{array}}v_S.}\) By
D , we obtain the following:
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _i(v_S)={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}v_S(\{i\})=\dfrac{v(\{i\})}{2^n-1} \text { for all } i \in N \text { and }|S|= 1, \text { and} \\ v_S(\{i\})=\dfrac{v(\{i\})}{2^n-1} \text { for all } i \in N,\, i \notin S,\,|S|\ge 2. \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
(6)
By Lemma
1 , all players
\(i \in S,\,|S|\ge 2,\) are pairwise weakly dependent in
\(v_S\) . We get for an arbitrary
\(i \in S,\,|S|\ge 2,\) and by
\(v_S(N)\underset{\begin{array}{c} (5) \end{array}}{=}\varDelta _v(S)+\sum _{j\in N}\dfrac{v(\{j\})}{2^n-1}\) :
$$\begin{aligned}{}\begin{array}[b]{rcl} \sum \nolimits _{j \in S}\varphi _j(v_S)&{}\underset{(\mathbf P )}{=}&{} \displaystyle {\sum _{j \in S}\frac{v_S(\{j\})}{v_S(\{i\})}\varphi _i(v_S)}= \sum _{j \in S}\frac{v(\{j\})}{v(\{i\})}\varphi _i(v_S)\\ &{}\underset{\begin{array}{c} (\mathbf E ) \end{array}}{=}&v_S(N)- \displaystyle {\sum _{j \in N\backslash S}\varphi _j(v_S)} \underset{\begin{array}{c} (6) \end{array}}{=}\varDelta _v(S)+\sum _{j\in S}\dfrac{v(\{j\})}{2^n-1} \\ \Leftrightarrow \;\;\varphi _i(v_S)&{}=&{} \displaystyle {\frac{v(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}v(\{j\})}\varDelta _v(S)}+ \frac{v(\{i\})}{2^n-1}. \end{array} \end{aligned}$$
(7)
Therefore, we have by (
3 ), (
6 ), and (
7 ) for all
\(S \subseteq N,\,S\ne \emptyset :\) $$\begin{aligned} \varphi _i(v_S)={\text {Sh}}^p_i(v_S) \text { for all } i\in N. \end{aligned}$$
\({\text {Sh}}^p\) and
\(\varphi \) satisfy
WA . It follows:
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _i(v)={\text {Sh}}_i^p(v) \text { for all }i \in N, \end{aligned}$$
and uniqueness is shown.
\(\square \) Proof of Proposition 1 \(\Rightarrow \) : We show that
WM implies
WCSE : Let
v and
w two TU-games satisfying the hypotheses of
WCSE , i.e. for a coalition
\(R \subseteq N, \,|R|\ge 2,\) \(c \in \mathbb {R},\) we have the following:
$$\begin{aligned} v(S)={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}w(S)+c, \text { if }S\supseteq R,\\ w(S),\text { if }S\nsupseteq R.\end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
Let
\(\varphi \) be a TU-value which obeys
WM . By Lemma
4 , we have
$$\begin{aligned} \varDelta _{v}(S)={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}\varDelta _w(R)+c,\text { if } S=R, \\ \varDelta _w(S), \text { otherwise.}\end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
Thus, we have
\(\varDelta _v(S \cup \{i\}) = \varDelta _w(S \cup \{i\})\) for all
\(i \in N\backslash R\) and
\(S \subseteq N\backslash \{i\}\) . It follows from Lemma
5 that
\({\text {MC}}_i^v(S)={\text {MC}}_i^w(S)\) for all
\(S \subseteq N\backslash \{i\}\) . Therefore, we can use
WM and get
\(\varphi _i(v)= \varphi _i(w)\, \text { for all } i \in N\backslash R\) and
WCSE is satisfied.
\(\Leftarrow \) : we show that
WCSE implies
WM : let
\(N \in \mathcal {N},\,i \in N,\,v,w \in \mathcal {G}^N\) two coalition functions satisfying the hypothesis of
WM , i.e.,
\({\text {MC}}_i^v(S)={\text {MC}}_i^w(S)\) for all
\(S \subseteq N\backslash \{i\}\) and
\(w(\{k\})= v(\{k\})\) for all
\(k \in N\) and
\(\varphi \) a value satisfying
WCSE . Then, by Lemma
5 , we have
\(\varDelta _v(T) = \varDelta _w(T)\) for all
\(T \subseteq N,\,T\ni i\) . Let
\(\mathcal {R}=\{R_j\subseteq N:\varDelta _v(R_j)\ne \varDelta _w(R_j) \}\) an indexed set of all subsets of
N with different dividends in
v and
w ,
\(1 \le j \le |\mathcal {R}|\) . We inductively define a sequence of coalition functions
\(w_j,\,0\le j \le |\mathcal {R}|,\) by
\(w_j:=w\) if
\(j=0\) , and, if
\(1\le j \le |\mathcal {R}|:\) $$\begin{aligned} \varDelta _{w_{j}}(S):={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}\varDelta _{w_{j-1}}(R_j)+\big [\varDelta _v(R_j)-\varDelta _{w_{j-1}}(R_j)\big ],\text { if } S=R_j, \\ \varDelta _{w_{j-1}}(S), \text { if }S\subseteq N, \,S\ne R_j.\end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
Then, we have
\(w_{|\mathcal {R}|}=v\) and, by Lemma
4 and
WCSE, we get
\( \varphi _i(w_{j})=\varphi _i(w_{j-1})\) for all
\(j,\, 1 \le j \le |\mathcal {R}|,\) and therefore,
\(\varphi _i(v)=\varphi _i(w)\) and
WM is satisfied.
\(\square \) Proof of Theorem 2 I. Existence: by Theorem 1 , \({\text {Sh}}^p\) satisfies E and P .
\(\bullet \) WCSE : By Lemma
4 , we have for
v and a coalition
R from
WCSE :
$$\begin{aligned} \varDelta _{v}(S)={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}\varDelta _w(R)+c,\text { if } S=R, \\ \varDelta _w(S), \text { otherwise}.\end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
Thus, we obtain for all
\(i\in N\backslash R\) by the following:
$$\begin{aligned} {\text {Sh}}^{p}_i(v) = \sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}v(\{j\})}\varDelta _v(S)=\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N,\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ w(\{i\})}{\sum _{j \in S}w(\{j\})}\varDelta _w(S)={\text {Sh}}^{p}_i(w). \end{aligned}$$
II. Uniqueness: Let
\(N\in \mathcal {N}, \,n:=|N|\) ,
\(v \in \mathcal {G}^{N}_{0}\) , and
\(\varphi \) a TU-value which satisfies all axioms of Theorem
2 . We will show that
\(\varphi \) satisfies Eq. (
3 ).
For \(n=1\) , Eq. (3 ) is satisfied by E .
Let \(n\ge 2\) . We use an induction on the size \(r:=|\{R \subseteq N: R \text { is active in } v\) and \(|R|\ge 2\}|\) .
Initialization: Let
\(r=0\) . By Lemma
1 , all players
\(i,j \in N\) are pairwise weakly dependent in
v . We get for an arbitrary
\(i \in N\) :
$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j \in N}\varphi _j(v)\underset{(\mathbf P )}{=} \sum _{j \in N}\frac{v(\{j\})}{v(\{i\})}\varphi _i(v)\underset{(\mathbf E )}{=}v(N). \end{aligned}$$
With
\(v(N)= \sum _{j \in N}v(\{j\})\) it follows that
\(\varphi _i(v) =v(\{i\})\) and Eq. (
3 ) holds to
\(\varphi \) if r = 0.
Induction step: Assume that Eq. (
3 ) holds to
\(\varphi \) if
\(r\ge 0,\,r\) arbitrary (
IH ), and let exactly
\(r+1\) coalitions
\(Q_k \subseteq N, \,|Q_k|\ge 2,\, 1\le k\le r+1,\) active in
v . Let
Q be the intersection of all such coalitions
\(Q_k\) :
$$\begin{aligned} Q=\bigcap _{1\le k\le r+1}Q_k. \end{aligned}$$
We distinguish two cases: (a)
\(i \in N\backslash Q\) and (b)
\(i \in Q\) .
(a) Each player
\(i \in N\backslash Q\) is a member of at most
r active coalitions
\(Q_k,\, |Q_k|\ge 2,\) and
v gets at least one active coalition
\(R_i,\,|R_i|\ge 2\) ,
\(i \notin R_i\) . Hence, there exists a coalition function
\(w_i\in \mathcal {G}^{N}_{0}\) , where all coalitions get the same dividend in
\(w_i\) as in
v , except coalition
\(R_i\) which gets the dividend
\(\varDelta _{w_i}(R_i)=0,\) and there is a scalar
\(c \in \mathbb {R},\,c\ne 0, \) with the following:
$$\begin{aligned} \varDelta _{v}(S)={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll}\varDelta _{w_i}(R_i)+c,\text { if } S=R_i, \\ \varDelta _{w_i}(S), \text { otherwise. }\end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$
By Lemma
4 and
WCSE , we get
\(\varphi _i(v)=\varphi _i(w_i) \text { with } i \in N\backslash R_i\) and because there exists for all
\(i \in N\backslash Q\) a such
\(R_i\) , we get
\(\varphi _i(v)=\varphi _i(w_i) \text { for all } i \in N\backslash Q\) . All coalition functions
\(w_i\) get at most
r active coalitions with at least two players and Eq. (
3 ) follows by (
IH ). Thus, we have the following:
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _i(v)={\text {Sh}}_i^p(v) \text { for all }i \in N\backslash Q. \end{aligned}$$
(8)
(b) If
\(Q=\{i\}\) , we get, by
E of
\(\varphi \) and
\({\text {Sh}}^p\) and case (a),
\( \varphi _i(v)= {\text {Sh}}^p_i(v)\) . If
\(|Q|\ge 2\) , each player
\(j \in Q\) is a member of all
\(r+1\) active coalitions
\(Q_k \subseteq N, \,|Q_k|\ge 2,\, 1\le k\le r+1,\) and therefore, by Lemma
1 , all players
\(j \in Q\) are weakly dependent. By
P and
E of
\(\varphi \) and
\({\text {Sh}}^p\) , we get for an arbitrary
\(i \in Q\) the following:
$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j \in Q}\varphi _j(v)&\underset{(\mathbf P )}{=} \sum _{j \in Q}\frac{v(\{j\})}{v(\{i\})}\varphi _i(v) \underset{\begin{array}{c} (\mathbf E )\\ (8) \end{array}}{=}v(N)- \sum _{j \in N\backslash Q}{\text {Sh}}^p_j(v)\underset{\begin{array}{c} (\mathbf E ) \end{array}}{=}\sum _{j \in Q}{\text {Sh}}^p_j(v)\\&\underset{(\mathbf P )}{=} \sum _{j \in Q}\frac{v(\{j\})}{v(\{i\})}{\text {Sh}}^p_i(v) \;\;\Leftrightarrow \;\;\varphi _i(v)={\text {Sh}}_i^p(v) \end{aligned}$$
and together with
I. the proof is complete.
\(\square \) Proof of Proposition 2 Let
\((N,v) \in \mathcal {G}_{0}^N,\,j \in N,\) and
\((N^j,v^j) \in \mathcal {G}_0^{N^j}\) a corresponding split player game to (
N ,
v ). We point out that we have for all
\(S \subseteq N\backslash \{j\},\, S \ne \emptyset ,\) \(\varDelta _{v^j}(S)=\varDelta _{v}(S),\) \(\varDelta _{v^j}(S\cup \{k,l\})=\varDelta _v(S\cup \{j\})\) , and
\(\varDelta _{v^j}(S\cup \{k\})=\varDelta _{v^j}(S\cup \{\ell \})=0\) . Then, we get for all
\(i \in N\backslash \{j\}\) the following:
$$\begin{aligned} {\text {Sh}}^{p}_i(N,v) =&\sum _{\begin{array}{c} R\subseteq N,\\ {R\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{m \in R}v(\{m\})}\varDelta _v(R)\\ =&\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N\backslash \{j\},\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{m \in S}v(\{m\})}\varDelta _v(S)\\&+\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N\backslash \{j\},\\ {S\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v(\{i\})}{\sum _{m \in S\cup \{j\}}v(\{m\})}\varDelta _v(S\cup \{j\}) \\ =&\sum _{\begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N^j\backslash \{k,\ell \},\\ {S \ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v^j(\{i\})}{\sum _{m \in S}v^j(\{m\})}\varDelta _{v^j}(S)\\&+\sum _{\begin{array}{c} \begin{array}{c} S\subseteq N^j\backslash \{k,\ell \},\\ {S\ni i} \end{array} \end{array}} \frac{ v^j(\{i\})}{\sum _{m \in S\cup \{k,\ell \}}v^j(\{m\})}\varDelta _{v^j}(S\cup \{k,\ell \})\\ =&\;\sum _{\begin{array}{c} R\subseteq N^j,\\ {R\ni i} \end{array}} \frac{ v^j(\{i\})}{\sum _{m \in R}v^j(\{m\})}\varDelta _{v^j}(R)\\ =&\;{\text {Sh}}^{p}_i(N^j,v^j). \end{aligned}$$
\(\square \) Proof of Lemma 2 Let
\(N=\{1,2,..., n\},\, |N|\ge 2\) ,
\(v \in \mathcal {G}_{0}^N\) ,
\(\varphi \) a TU-value which satisfies
E and
PS for all
\(v \in \mathcal {G}_{0}^N\) , and w.l.o.g., player 1 and player 2 be symmetric in
v . If we split player 1 according to
PS into two new players, player
\(n+1\) and player
\(n+2\) ,
\(N^1= \{2,3,...,n, n+1, n+2\}\) , we have the following:
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _{2}(N^1,v^1)= \varphi _{2}(N,v), \end{aligned}$$
(9)
and, if we split player 2 according to
PS into the same players as before, player
\(n+1\) and player
\(n+2\) , instead,
\(N^2= \{1,3, 4,...,n, n+1, n+2\}\) , we have the following:
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _{1}(N^2,v^2)= \varphi _{1}(N,v), \end{aligned}$$
(10)
where we choose
\(v^2(\{n+1\}):=v^1(\{n+1\})\) and
\(v^2(\{n+2\}):=v^1(\{n+2\})\) .
In the same manner, we split now in the game
\((N^1, v^1)\) player 2 into two new players, player
\(n+3\) and player
\(n+4\) , and analogous in the game
\((N^2, v^2)\) player 1 into the same players as before, player
\(n+3\) and player
\(n+4\) , and choose
\({v^{2}}^1(\{n+3\}):={v^{1}}^2(\{n+3\})\) and
\({v^{2}}^1(\{n+4\}):={v^{1}}^2(\{n+4\})\) . We have
\({N^{1}}^2={N^{2}}^1=\{3,4,..., n,n+1,n+2,n+3,n+4\}\) and
\({v^{1}}^2={v^{2}}^1\) and get by
E , according to Remark
1 :
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _{n+3}\Big ({{N^1}^2,{v^1}^2}\Big )+\varphi _{n+4}\Big ({{N^1}^2,{v^1}^2}\Big )&= \varphi _{2}(N^1,v^1)\underset{(9)}{=}\varphi _{2}(N,v),\\ \varphi _{n+3}\Big ({{N^{2}}^1,{v^2}^1}\Big )+\varphi _{n+4}\Big ({{N^{2}}^1,{v^2}^1}\Big )&= \varphi _{1}(N^2,v^2)\underset{(10)}{=}\varphi _{1}(N,v). \end{aligned}$$
Hence, we have
\(\varphi _{1}(N,v)= \varphi _{2}(N,v)\) and
S is shown.
\(\square \) Proof of Lemma 3 Let \(N \in \mathcal {N},\, |N|\ge 2\) , \(v \in \mathcal {G}_{0_{\mathbb {Q}}}^N\) a TU-game, and, w.l.o.g., players \(i,j \in N\) , such that i and j are weakly dependent in v . Furthermore, let \(\varphi \) a TU-value which satisfies E and PS for all \(v \in \mathcal {G}_{0_{\mathbb {Q}}}^N\) , and therefore, by Lemma 2 , also S . Due to \(v(\{i\}),v(\{j\}) \in \mathbb {Q}\backslash \{0\}\) , the worths of the singletons \(v(\{k\}),\,k \in \{i,j\}\) , can be written as a fraction. We distinguish two cases: (a) \(v(\{k\})>0\) and (b) \(v(\{k\})<0\) .
(a) We have the following:
$$\begin{aligned} v(\{k\})=\;\dfrac{p_k}{q_k} \;\text { with }\; p_k,q_k \in \mathbb {N}. \end{aligned}$$
We choose a main denominator
q of these two fractions by
\(q:=q_iq_j\) . With
\(z_i:= p_iq_j\) and
\(z_j:= p_jq_i\) , we get the following:
$$\begin{aligned} v(\{i\})= \;\frac{z_i}{q}\;\text { and }\;v(\{j\})= \;\frac{z_j}{q}. \end{aligned}$$
(11)
Now, we define a player set
\(N'\) and a coalition function
\(v'\) by “splitting” each player
\( k \in \{i,j\}\) into
\(z_k\) players
\(k_{1}\) to
\(k_{z_k}\) , such that we have
\(N'=(N\backslash \{i,j\})\cup \{i_m: 1\le m \le z_i\}\cup \{j_m: 1\le m \le z_j\}\) . Each player
\(k_{m}\in N'\backslash (N\backslash \{i,j\}),\,\, 1\le m \le z_k,\) gets a singleton worth
\(v'(\{k_{m}\})=\frac{1}{q} \text { for } k \in \{i,j\}\) , synonymous with
$$\begin{aligned} v'(\{\ell \})= \frac{1}{q} \text { for all } \ell \in N'\backslash (N\backslash \{i,j\}), \end{aligned}$$
where
\(|N'\backslash (N\backslash \{i,j\})|=z_i +z_j\) and
\(v(\{k\})= \sum _{1\le m \le z_k}v'(\{k_{m}\}),\,k \in \{i,j\}\) . We define
\(v'(R'):=v(R)\) for all
\(R'= R\backslash \{i,j\} \cup N'\backslash (N\backslash \{i,j\}),\, R \subseteq N, \{i,j\}\subseteq R,\) and
\(v'(S):= v(S)\) for all
\(S\subseteq N'\) with
\(S\subseteq N\) . All other coalitions
\(T\subseteq N'\) are defined as not active in
\(v'\) .
Applying
PS (repeatedly) to
\(v,\; \varphi \) and the two players
\(i,j \in N\) , we can get the coalition function
\(v'\) defined just before and, by Remark
1 , we have the following:
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _k(N,v) = \sum _{1\le m \le z_k}\varphi _{k_{m}}(N',v') \text { for } k \in \{i,j\}. \end{aligned}$$
(12)
All players
\(\ell \in N'\backslash (N\backslash \{i,j\})\) are symmetric in
\(v'\) . Hence, it follows from
S that
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _{\ell }(N',v')=\,\frac{\varphi _i(N,v)+\varphi _j(N,v)}{z_i+z_j}\text { for all } \ell \in N'\backslash (N\backslash \{i,j\}). \end{aligned}$$
We get
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _k(N,v)\underset{(12)}{=}\,\sum _{1\le m \le z_k}\varphi _{k_{m}}(N',v')=\frac{z_k}{z_i+z_j}\big [\varphi _i(N,v)+\varphi _j(N,v)\big ]\text { for } k \in \{i,j\}. \end{aligned}$$
It follows:
$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _i(N,v) = \frac{z_i}{z_j}\varphi _j(N,v)\underset{(11)}{=} \frac{v(\{i\})}{v(\{j\})}\varphi _j(N,v) \end{aligned}$$
and
P is shown.
(b) We have the following:
$$\begin{aligned} v(\{k\})=\;\dfrac{p_k}{q_k} \;\text { with }\; (-p_k),q_k \in \mathbb {N}. \end{aligned}$$
We choose a main denominator
q of these two fractions by
\(q:=-q_iq_j\) . With
\(z_i:= -p_iq_j\) and
\(z_j:= -p_jq_i\) , we get
$$\begin{aligned} v(\{i\})= \;\frac{z_i}{q}\;\text { and }\;v(\{j\})= \;\frac{z_j}{q}. \end{aligned}$$
The remaining part of the proof equals the related part in case (a).
\(\square \) Logical independence Finally, we want to show the independence of the axioms used in the characterizations.
References Amer, R., Carreras, F., & Magaña, A. (2007). Two main methods for utility sharing in joint business: A discussion.
Journal of Mathematics and Statistics ,
3 (1), 28–35.
Google Scholar Banker, R. D. (1981).
Equity considerations in traditional full cost allocation practices: An axiomatic perspective . Pittsburgh: Carnegie-Mellon University.
Google Scholar Barton, T. L. (1988). Intuitive choice of cooperative sharing mechanisms for joint cost savings: Some empirical results.
Abacus ,
24 (2), 162–169.
Google Scholar Béal, S., Ferrières, S., Rémila, E., & Solal, P. (2018). The proportional Shapley value and applications.
Games and Economic Behavior ,
108 , 93–112.
Google Scholar Besner, M. (2016). Lösungskonzepte kooperativer Spiele mit Koalitionsstrukturen, Master’s thesis at the Chair of Discrete Mathematics, FernUniversität in Hagen (in German).
Google Scholar van den Brink, R., Levínský, R., & Zelený, M. (2015). On proper Shapley values for monotone TU-games.
International Journal of Game Theory ,
44 (2), 449–471.
Google Scholar Casajus, A., & Huettner, F. (2008). Marginality is equivalent to coalitional strategic equivalence. Working paper.
Google Scholar Chun, Y. (1989). A new axiomatization of the Shapley value.
Games and Economic Behavior ,
1 (2), 119–130.
Google Scholar Chun, Y. (1991). On symmetric and weighted Shapley values.
International Journal of Game Theory ,
20 (2), 183–190.
Google Scholar Dehez, P., & Tellone, D. (2013). Data games: Sharing public goods with exclusion.
Journal of Public Economic Theory ,
15 (4), 654–673.
Google Scholar Feldman, B. (1999).
The proportional value of a cooperative game. Manuscript . Chicago: Scudder Kemper Investments.
Google Scholar Gangolly, J. S. (1981). On joint cost allocation: Independent cost proportional scheme (ICPS) and its properties.
Journal of Accounting Research, 299–312.
Google Scholar Harsanyi, J. C. (1959). A bargaining model for cooperative n-person games. In A. W. Tucker & R. D. Luce (Eds.),
Contributions to the theory of games IV (pp. 325–355). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar Hart, S., & Mas-Colell, A. (1989). Potential, value, and consistency.
Econometrica ,
57 (3), 589–614.
Google Scholar Huettner, F. (2015). A proportional value for cooperative games with a coalition structure.
Theory and Decision ,
78 (2), 273–287.
Google Scholar Kalai, E., & Samet, D. (1987). On weighted Shapley values.
International Journal of Game Theory ,
16 (3), 205–222.
Google Scholar Leng, M., & Parlar, M. (2009). Allocation of cost savings in a three-level supply chain with demand information sharing: A cooperative-game approach.
Operations Research ,
57 (1), 200–213.
Google Scholar Moriarity, S. (1975). Another approach to allocating joint costs.
The Accounting Review ,
50 (4), 791–795.
Google Scholar Myerson, R. B. (1980). Conference structures and fair allocation rules.
International Journal of Game Theory ,
9 (3), 169–182.
Google Scholar von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944).
Theory of games and economic behavior . Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar Nowak, A. S., & Radzik, T. (1995). On axiomatizations of the weighted Shapley values.
Games and Economic Behavior ,
8 (2), 389–405.
Google Scholar Ortmann, K. M. (2000). The proportional value for positive cooperative games.
Mathematical Methods of Operations Research ,
51 (2), 235–248.
Google Scholar Radzik, T. (2012). A new look at the role of players’ weights in the weighted Shapley value.
European Journal of Operational Research ,
223 (2), 407–416.
Google Scholar Roth, A. E., & Verrecchia, R. E. (1979). The Shapley value as applied to cost allocation: A reinterpretation.
Journal of Accounting Research, 295–303.
Google Scholar Shapley, L. S. (1953).
Additive and non-additive set functions . Princeton: Princeton University.
Google Scholar Shapley, L. S. (1953). A value for n-person games. In H. W. Kuhn & A. W. Tucker (Eds.),
Contributions to the theory of games (Vol. 2, pp. 307–317). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Google Scholar Shubik, M. (1962). Incentives, decentralized control, the assignment of joint costs and internal pricing.
Management Science ,
8 (3), 325–343.
Google Scholar Spinetto, R. D. (1975). Fairness in cost allocations and cooperative games.
Decision Sciences ,
6 (3), 482–491.
Google Scholar Thomas, A. L. (1969).
The allocation problem in financial accounting theory-studies in accounting research no 3 . Evanston, IL: American Accounting Association.
Google Scholar Thomas, A. L. (1974).
The allocation problem in financial accounting theory (No. 9) . Evanston, IL: American Accounting Association.
Google Scholar Tijs, S. H., & Driessen, T. S. (1986). Extensions of solution concepts by means of multiplicative
\(\varepsilon \) -tax games.
Mathematical Social Sciences ,
12 (1), 9–20.
Google Scholar Young, H. P. (1985). Monotonic solutions of Cooperative Games.
International Journal of Game Theory ,
14 (2), 65–72.
Google Scholar Young, H. P. (1985).
Cost Allocation: Methods, Principles, Applications . : North Holland Publishing Co.
Google Scholar © Springer Science+Business Media, LLC, part of Springer Nature 2019
Authors and Affiliations 1. Department of Geomatics, Computer Science and Mathematics HFT Stuttgart, University of Applied Sciences Stuttgart Germany