Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Gendering animals

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we argue that there are good, scientifically credible reasons for thinking that some nonhuman animals might have genders. We begin by considering why the sex/gender distinction has been important for feminist politics yet has also been difficult to maintain. We contrast contemporary views that trouble gender with those typical of traditional sex difference research, which has enjoyed considerable feminist critique, and argue that the anthropocentric focus of feminist accounts of gender weakens these critiques. Then, drawing from Jordan-Young’s concept of gendered norms of reaction (2010) and van Anders’ Sexual Configurations Theory (2015), we consider what it might mean to say that animals other than humans are gendered in a scientifically robust sense that does not simply reduce gender to sex or project human gender norms onto other animals. It is important that such an account is not only sensitive to its political ramifications for feminist and queer politics but is also sensitive to the ways in which troubling the human–nonhuman animal divide may seem to threaten those humans whose oppression is constituted by dehumanization and animalization. We suggest that, in fact, the contrary is true. We find that decolonial feminists have plausibly argued that animalizing oppression is premised on the human–animal divide and that the idea of nonhuman animal genders fits naturally with some traditional Indigenous ways of thinking about other animals and their relations with humans.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As one of us has noted elsewhere, there is no agreed upon term that picks out the cultures that are rooted in the Greco-Roman Christianized world and are now present in various regions globally due to the European project of colonialism in the modern period (Meynell 2009, pp. 1–2). None of them are wholly satisfactory and we have here chosen the term “Global North.”

  2. Although published in The Politics of Reality in 1983, Frye notes that she had developed the main themes of this paper as early as 1974.

  3. See Nicholson’s “Interpreting Gender” (1994) and Mikkola’s “Feminist Perspectives on Sex and Gender” (2019) for a rather less cursory overview.

  4. See Blackless et al. (2000) for a useful discussion of absolute versus moderate sex dimorphism.

  5. Larry Cahill’s review of Gina Rippon’s Gender and Our Brains (2019) basically plays out this kind of argument, as does Jerry Coyne’s review of Fine’s Testosterone Rex (2017).

  6. For instance, in Bodies That Matter (1993) Butler neither presumes nor negates materiality (1993, p. 30). She argues that we “discover that matter is fully sedimented with discourses on sex and sexuality that prefigure and constrain the uses to which that term can be put” (p. 29).

  7. The point here is not that the way these sex differences are treated, say in the medical world, is not thoroughly imbued with and shaped by social values, but rather that no matter what shape these institutions might have they will still need to cope with basic sexed bodily functions, such as puberty, menstruation, ejaculation, pregnancy, and so forth.

  8. Van Anders explains, “Partner number sexuality refers to the number of partners people have or are interested in having. For example, someone might want to have no partners, one partner, two partners concurrently, or more” (2015, p. 1193).

  9. One of Jordan-Young’s examples makes this point forcefully—the “very low bone mineral density in the lower back among ultra-Orthodox Jewish adolescents” (2010, p. 285). Although typically in this age group bone density is higher on average in boys than girls, in this population this is inverted. Moreover, “the sex difference was found even after [the researchers] controlled for [environmental factors associated with higher bone density], such as hours per week of weight-bearing exercise and walking” (p. 285).

  10. This definition is in line with Whitehead and Rendell’s definition of culture: “culture is information or behavior—shared within a community—which is acquired from conspecifics through some form of social learning” (2015, p. 12). However, it requires an important proviso. Nonbinary gender identities and traits are neither correlated nor culturally integrated with sex yet must nonetheless be distinguished from non-gender traits that have sociocultural and historical causes (like speaking Spanish, wearing a hanbok, or using a fork). We propose that nonbinary genders and gender traits exist only in cultures with binary genders and can only emerge in reaction and relation to binary gender identities and traits. What the details of a given nonhuman nonbinary gender might be are not entirely clear but must be considered species by species. We note that cultures with a gender binary may evolve to have three distinct genders and, concomitantly, there is the possibility that cultures with three distinct genders might have non-ternary genders, and so on.

  11. It is not clear that we should include all types of social learning as evidence of culture. Whitehead and Rendell provide a useful list of social learning processes, differing in “complexity and cognitive demand” from stimulus enhancement to emulation (2015, pp. 16–17). Whether only those species that display complex and cognitively demanding types of social learning are capable of having cultures is an important question that must be left to a later discussion.

  12. While the restrictions of space limit a fulsome discussion of other examples, we can at least gesture toward a couple of other promising cases. For chimpanzees, it is plausible that at least some of their hunting practices are socially learned; considered at the level of species, hunting is strongly sex-linked with males. However, female participation differs significantly between communities (Pruetz et al. 2015, p. 9). Most notably, the practice of hunting with modified “spearing” tools (Pruetz and Bertolani 2007), used only by a community of chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes verus) at Fongoli, Sénégal, is practiced more by females than males (Pruetz et al. 2015). This suggests that various hunting practices are gender or perhaps gender/sex traits. (We leave readers to make their own inferences about what this finding might suggest for “man the tool-making hunter” hypotheses in evolutionary psychology.).

    Another interesting place one might look for gender is in sperm whale (Physeter macrocephalus) cultures. While adult male sperm whales live mostly solitary lives, female sperm whales have clear communities, the structure of which differ between oceans (Whitehead and Rendell 2015, p. 148). Given our definition, any socially learned adult behavior that is specific to a family unit or clan will be gender or gender-sex. Perhaps more interesting is the possibility that within a community there might be distinct socially learned roles among the females, meaning there could be two (or more) genders among females. So, it is possible that there could be two (or more) female genders and no male gender among sperm whales.

    While it is tempting to include examples of same-sex sexual behavior here, we must be cautious. Unless a behavior is socially learned and culturally contingent it is not gender as we have defined it. Moreover, as SCT reveals, the relationship between sexual behavior and gender is complicated and the two can be conceptually distinguished. For instance, the well-known same-sex sexual behavior among bighorn sheep (Ovis canadensis) (Roughgarden 2004, pp. 137–40) may be biologically driven and thus have no relationship to gender. However, if such behavior is socially learned or has a socially learned component, then it will be a gender or gender-sex trait.

  13. We note that the chimpanzees at Arnhem were brought together not by families and lineages, but by human intervention in a place far from the typical chimpanzee habitat, meaning that the social structure of their community was likely quite anomalous. Nonetheless, like humans, chimpanzees are biologically social animals, and the Arnhem colony would have developed certain social practices. Whether some of these were passed down from the norms of free-living populations could only be ascertained by a careful examination of the personal histories of the founding members of the group.

  14. We note that this elision is not unique to discussions of gender but rather applies to any account that finds in nonhuman animals any morally or politically relevant capacity (in effect, any affective, cognitive, and social trait) that has been thought to be uniquely human. It is particularly fraught when the trait in question is considered central to conceptions of human rights, as is the case, for instance, with autonomy.

  15. Lugones writes that “often, when social scientists investigate colonized societies, the search for the sexual distinction and then the construction of the gender distinction results from observations of the tasks performed by each sex” (p. 744). Sexual dimorphism then comes to ground a dichotomous understanding of gender, to the point where sex and gender are conflated. We believe that SCT successfully resolves this concern.

  16. Some may wonder how these kinds of respectful relationships are consistent with hunting. There are a diversity of views among Indigenous people on hunting and food ethics and their relation to Indigenous culture and sovereignty (e.g., Belcourt 2019; Coté 2010; Fisher 2011; Koleszar-Green and Matsuoka 2018; Peterson and Hogan 2002; Robinson 2016; Robinson 2018; TallBear 2019; Womack 2013; see also Kim 2015, Ch. 7; Russell 1999;). Many Indigenous authors stress the importance of taking no more than one needs and maintaining attitudes of gratitude and reciprocity for whatever one takes, including the lives of other animals (Coulthard 2014; Deloria 1991/1997; Kimmerer 2013; Robinson 2014). Within the constraints of subsistence hunting, various rituals are required to remain in good relations with the animals killed. In a book for Indigenous children on their relations with nonhuman animals, Deloria writes, “other creatures do have thought processes, emotions, personal relationships and many of the experiences we have in our lives. We must carefully accord these other creatures the respect that they deserve and the right to live without unnecessary harm. Wanton killings of different animals by some hunters and sportsmen are completely outside the traditional way that native people have treated other species” (1991/1997, p. xii). This reflects what Glen Coulthard refers to as “grounded normativity,” a relationship to land and its inhabitants based on reciprocity (2014, p. 60; Coulthard and Simpson 2016, p. 254). This normativity is not merely ethical, but political, with the political interest and agency of nonhuman animals being held as important (e.g., Hogan 1998; Hudson 2015; Mohawk 1988).

References

  • Adams, C. (1994/2018). Neither man nor beast: Feminism and the defense of animals. New York, NY: Bloomsbury.

  • Adams, C. (2000). The sexual politics of meat (Tenth anniversary edition). New York, NY: Continuum.

  • Allen, P. G. (1986). The sacred hoop: Recovering the feminine in American Indian traditions. New York, NY: Open Road Integrated Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barash, D. (2005). Let a thousand orgasms bloom. Review of The Case of the Female Orgasm, by Elisabeth Lloyd. Evolutionary Psychology, 3, 347–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belcourt, B.-R. (2019). Thinking paradoxically. In S. King, R. S. Carey, I. Macquarrie, V. N. Millious, & E. M. Power (Eds.), Messy eating: Conversations on animals as food (pp. 233–241). New York, NY: Fordham University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackless, M., Charuvastra, A., Derryck, A., Fausto-Sterling, A., Lauzanne, K., & Lee, E. (2000). How sexually dimorphic are we? Review and synthesis. American Journal of Human Biology, 12(2), 151–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, B., Jetten, J., & Haslam, N. (2013). An interpersonal perspective on dehumanization. In P. G. Bain, J. Vaes, & J. P. Leyens (Eds.), Humanness and dehumanization (pp. 205–224). New York, NY: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1993). Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of “sex.” New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cahill, L. (2019). Denying the neuroscience of sex differences. Quillette. https://quillette.com/2019/03/29/denying-the-neuroscience-of-sex-differences/. Accessed 20 July, 2020.

  • Coté, C. (2010). Spirits of our whaling ancestors: Revitalizing Makah and Nuu-chah-nulth traditions. Seattle, WA: University of Washington.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulthard, G. S. (2014). Red skin, white masks: Rejecting the colonial politics of recognition. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coulthard, G. S., & Simpson, L. B. (2016). Grounded normativity/Place-based solidarity. American Quarterly, 68(2), 249–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coyne, J. (2017). “Testosterone Rex”, a biased polemic, wins the Royal Society book prize. Why Evolution Is True. https://whyevolutionistrue.wordpress.com/2017/09/21/testosterone-rex-a-biased-polemic-wins-the-royal-society-book-prize/. Accessed 20 July, 2020.

  • Crenshaw, K. (1991). Mapping the margins: Intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against women of color. Stanford Law Review, 43(6), 1241–1299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummings, S. R., Ling, X., & Stone, K. (1997). Consequences of foot binding among older women in Beijing, China. American Journal of Public Health, 87(10), 1677–1679.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F. B. M. (1982/1998). Chimpanzee politics: Power and sex among apes (Revised). Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University.

  • Deloria, Jr., V. (1991/1997). Foreword. In M. J. Caduto & J. Bruchac (Eds.), Keepers of the animals: Native American stories and wildlife activities for children (pp. xi–xii). Wheat Ridge, CO: Fulcrum Resources.

  • Deloria, V., Jr. (2001). American Indian metaphysics. In V. Deloria & D. Wildcat (Eds.), Power and place: Indian education in America (pp. 1–6). Wheat Ridge, CO: Fulcrum Resources.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. (2008). The animal that therefore I am (M.-L. Mallet, Ed.; D. Wills, Trans.). New York, NY: Fordham University.

  • Diamond, J. (1995). Father’s milk. Discover, 16(2), 82–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabian, J. (2018). Trump on MS-13: ‘These are not people, these are animals.’ The Hill. https://thehill.com/homenews/administration/389037-trump-on-ms-13-these-are-not-people-these-are-animals.

  • Fausto-Sterling, A. (2000). Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York, NY: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fausto-Sterling, A. (2012). Sex/gender: Biology in a social world. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenton, A. (2018). Decisional authority and animal research subjects. In K. Andrews & J. Beck (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds (pp. 475–484). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, C. (2010). Delusions of gender: How our minds, society, and neurosexism create difference. New York, NY: W. W. Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, C. (2017). Testosterone Rex: Myths of sex, science, and society. New York, NY: W. W. Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, L. (2011). Freeing feathered spirits. In L. Kemmerer (Ed.), Sister species: Women, animals, and social justice (pp. 110–116). Champaign, IL: University of Illinois.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frye, M. (1983). The politics of reality: Essays in feminist theory. Trumansburg, NY: Crossing Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammarström, A., & Annandale, E. (2012). A conceptual muddle: An empirical analysis of the use of ‘sex’ and ‘gender’ in ‘gender-specific medicine’ . PLoS ONE, 7(4), e34193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (2008). When species meet. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogan, L. (1998). First People. In L. Hogan, D. Metzger, & B. Peterson (Eds.), Intimate nature: The bond between women and animals (pp. 6–19). New York, NY: Ballantine.

    Google Scholar 

  • hooks, b. (1984). Feminist theory: From margin to center. Boston, MA: South End Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, P. D. (1996). Gender treachery: Homophobia, masculinity, and threatened identities. In L. May, R. Strikwerda, & P. D. Hopkins (Eds.), Rethinking masculinity: Philosophical explorations in light of feminism (2nd ed., pp. 95–118). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, B. K. (2015). A seat at the table: Political representation for animals. In D. L. Madsen (Ed.), The Routledge companion to Native American literature (pp. 229–237). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan-Young, R. (2010). Brain storm: The flaws in the science of sex difference. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, C. J. (2011). Moral extensionism or racist exploitation? The use of Holocaust and slavery analogies in the animal liberation movement. New Political Science, 33(3), 311–333.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, C. J. (2015). Dangerous crossings: Race, species, and nature in a multicultural age. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, C. J. (2017). Murder and mattering at Harambe’s house. Politics and Animals, 3, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kimmerer, R. W. (2013). Braiding sweetgrass: Indigenous wisdom, scientific knowledge, and the teachings of plants. Minneapolis, MN: Milkweed Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ko, A. (2019). Racism as zoological witchcraft: A guide to Getting Out. Brooklyn, NY: Lantern Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ko, A., & Ko, S. (2017). Aphro-ism: Essays on pop culture, feminism, and Black veganism from two sisters. Brooklyn, NY: Lantern Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koleszar-Green, R., & Matsuoka, A. (2018). Indigenous worldviews and critical animal studies: Decolonization and revealing truncated narratives of dominance. In A. Matsuoka & R. R. Simonsen (Eds.), Critical animal studies: Towards trans-species social justice (pp. 333–350). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lorde, A. (1986). Our dead behind us: Poems. New York, NY: W. W. Norton and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lugones, M. (2010). Toward a decolonial feminism. Hypatia, 25(4), 742–759.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lugones, M. C., & Spelman, E. V. (1983). Have we got a theory for you! Feminist theory, cultural imperialism and the demand for ‘the woman’s voice.’ Women’s Studies International Forum, 6(6), 573–581.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald, T. K. (2019). Lactation care for transgender and non-binary patients: Empowering clients and avoiding aversives. Journal of Human Lactation, 35(2), 223–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meynell, L. (2008). The power and promise of developmental systems theory. Les Ateliers de l’Ethique, 3(2), 88–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meynell, L. (2009). Introduction: Minding bodies. In S. Campbell, L. Meynell, & S. Sherwin (Eds.), Embodiment and agency (pp. 1–22). University Park, PA: Penn State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meynell, L. (2012). Evolutionary psychology, ethology, and essentialism (because what they don’t know can hurt us). Hypatia, 27(1), 3–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meynell, L. (2016). Feminist studies of science. In N. A. Naples, et al. (Eds.), Wiley-Blackwell encyclopedia of gender and sexuality studies. New York, NY: Wiley. https://doi.org/10.1002/9781118663219.wbegss031.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mikkola, M. (2019). Feminist perspectives on sex and gender, The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2019), E. N. Zalta (Ed.) https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/feminism-gender/.

  • Mohawk, J. (1988). Animal nations and their right to survive. Daybreak, 19–22.

  • Moraga, C. L., & Anzaldúa, G. E. (Eds.). (1981). This bridge called my back: Writings by radical women of color. Chicago, IL: Third Woman Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, M. K. (2017). Getting dirty: The eco-eroticism of women in Indigenous oral literatures. In J. Barker (Ed.), Critically sovereign: Indigenous gender, sexuality, and feminist studies (pp. 229–260). Durham, NC: Duke University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, L. (1994). Interpreting gender. Signs, 20(1), 79–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, B., & Hogan, L. (2002). Sightings: The gray whales’ mysterious journey. Washington, DC: National Geographic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pruetz, J. D., & Bertolani, P. (2007). Savanna chimpanzees, Pan troglodytes verus, hunt with tools. Current Biology, 17, 412–417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pruetz, J. D., Bertolani, P., Boyer Ontl, K., Lindshield, S., Shelley, M., & Wessling, E. G. (2015). New evidence on the tool-assisted hunting exhibited by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes verus) in a savannah habitat at Fongoli, Sénégal. Royal Society Open Science. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsos.140507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quijano, A. (1992). Colonialidad y modernidad/racionalidad. PerúIndígena, 13(29), 11–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rich, A. (1980). Compulsory heterosexuality and lesbian existence. Signs, 5(4), 631–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, S. S. (2013). Sex itself: The search for male and female in the human genome. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rippon, G. (2019). Gender and our brains: How new neuroscience explodes the myth of the male and female minds. New York, NY: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, M. (2014). Animal personhood in Mi’kmaq perspective. Societies, 4(4), 672–688. https://doi.org/10.3390/soc4040672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, M. (2016). Is the Moose still my brother if we don’t eat im? In J. Castricano & R. R. Simonsen (Eds.), Critical perspectives on veganism (pp. 261–284). New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, M. (2018). The roots of my Indigenous veganism. In A. Matsuoka & J. Sorenson (Eds.), Critical animal studies: Towards trans-species social Justice (pp. 319–332). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, J. (2004). Evolution’s rainbow: Diversity, gender, and sexuality in nature and people. Berkley, CA: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, D. (1999). Tribal tradition and the spirit of trust. The Amicus Journal, 21(1), 29+.

  • Schiebinger, L. (1989). The mind has no sex? Women in the origins of modern science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soh, D. W. (2017). Op-Ed: Are gender feminists and transgender activists undermining science? Los Angeles Times. https://www.latimes.com/opinion/op-ed/la-oe-soh-trans-feminism-anti-science-20170210-story.html. Accessed 20 July 2020.

  • TallBear, K. (2011). Why interspecies thinking needs Indigenous standpoints. Fieldsights, November 18. https://culanth.org/fieldsights/why-interspecies-thinking-needs-indigenous-standpoints. Accessed 20 July 2020.

  • TallBear, K. (2019). Being in relation. In S. King, R. S. Carey, I. Macquarrie, V. N. Millious, & E. M. Power (Eds.), Messy eating: Conversations on animals as food (pp. 54–67). New York, NY: Fordham University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, S. (2017). Beasts of burden: Animal and disability liberation. New York, NY: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Anders, S. (2015). Beyond sexual orientation: Integrating gender/sex and diverse sexualities via sexual configuration theory. Archives of Sexual Behavior, 44, 1177–1213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, H., & Rendell, L. (2015). The cultural lives of whales and dolphins. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Womack, C. (2013). There is no respectful way to kill an animal. Studies in American Indian Literatures, 25(4), 11–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, D. (2005). The step back: Ethics and politics after deconstruction. Albany, NY: State University of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynter, S. (1994). No humans involved: An open letter to my colleagues. Institute N.H.I., 1(1), 42–73.

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank audiences at meetings of the Canadian Society for the History and Philosophy of Science and the Canadian Society for Women in Philosophy, as well as those who attended presentations of various drafts at the University of Calgary, Laurentian University, and Dalhousie University, for their thoughtful feedback. Our conversations with Andrew Fenton, Erik Nelson, Sofie Vlaad, and Emily Bingeman have also been invaluable, and we thank the anonymous reviewers and Noah Trammell for their careful reading and helpful advice. We gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Letitia Meynell.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Meynell, L., Lopez, A. Gendering animals. Synthese 199, 4287–4311 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02979-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02979-4

Keywords

Navigation