Advertisement

Synthese

pp 1–40 | Cite as

The (un)detectability of absolute Newtonian masses

  • Niels C. M. MartensEmail author
Article
  • 13 Downloads

Abstract

Absolutism about mass claims that mass ratios obtain in virtue of absolute masses. Comparativism denies this. Dasgupta (in: Bennett, Zimmerman (eds), Oxford studies in metaphysics, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013) argues for comparativism about mass, in the context of Newtonian Gravity. Such an argument requires proving that comparativism is empirically adequate. Dasgupta equates this to showing that absolute masses are undetectable, and attempts to do so. This paper develops an argument by Baker to the contrary: absolute masses are in fact empirically meaningful, that is detectable (in some weak sense). Additionally, it is argued that the requirement of empirical adequacy should not be cashed out in terms of undetectability in the first place. The paper closes by sketching the possible strategies that remain for the comparativist. Along the way a framework is developed that is useful for thinking about these issues: Ozma games—how could one explain to an alien civilisation what an absolute mass is?

Keywords

Physical quantities Comparativism Absolutism Mass Newtonian gravity Detectability 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank David Baker, Harvey Brown, Adam Caulton, Eddy Keming Chen, Erik Curiel, Shamik Dasgupta, Neil Dewar, Patrick Dürr, Sam Fletcher, Dennis Lehmkuhl, Niels Linnemann, Tushar Menon, Thomas Møller-Nielsen, Zee Perry, Oliver Pooley, Carina Prunkl, John Roberts, Simon Saunders, Syman Stevens, Reinier van Straten, Chris Timpson, Teru Tomas, David Wallace and Alastair Wilson for useful discussions, comments on earlier drafts of this essay, and for their generosity with their time. I am grateful for questions and comments from the audiences at the Ockham Society, the Socrates Society, the DPhil seminar, the Philosophy of Physics Research Seminar and the Philosophy of Physics Graduate Lunch Seminar at the University of Oxford, as well as SOPhiA 2014 in Salzburg, the 2014 Bucharest Graduate Conference in Early Modern Philosophy, the 2014 and 2015 Tübingen Summer Schools in HPS, the 2015 Metaphysics of Quantities Conference at NYU, the 2015 Graduate Workshop in Mathematical Philosophy at the MCMP in Munich, and the DPG2015 in Berlin. This material is based on work supported by the Arts and Humanities Research Council of the UK, a Scatcherd European Scholarship, and in part by the DFG Research Unit “The Epistemology of the Large Hadron Collider” (Grant FOR 2063). The major part of this essay was written while I was at Magdalen College and Department of Philosophy, University of Oxford, including a two-month research visit to Princeton University (supported by the AHRC Research Training Support Scheme and a Santander Academic Travel Award).

References

  1. Alexander, H. G. (Ed.). (1956). The Leibniz–Clarke correspondence. Manchester: Manchester University Press. (originally written by Leibniz, G.W. & Clarke, S. in 1715–16 and published by Clarke, S. in 1717.).Google Scholar
  2. Armstrong, D. (1978). A theory of universals: Volume 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Armstrong, D. (1988). Are quantities relations? A reply to bigelow and pargetter. Philosophical Studies, 54, 305–316.Google Scholar
  4. Arntzenius, F. (2000). Are there really instantaneous velocities? The Monist, 83(2), 187–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Arntzenius, F. (2012). Space, time, & stuff. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Baker, D. J. (2013a). Comparativism with mixed relations.Google Scholar
  7. Baker, D. J. (2013b). Some consequences of physics for the comparative metaphysics of quantity.Google Scholar
  8. Barbour, J. (2000). The end of time: The next revolution in physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Bauer, W. A. (2011). An argument for the extrinsic grounding of mass. Erkenntnis, 74(1), 81–99.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Belot, G. (1999). Rehabilitating relationalism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13(1), 35–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Belot, G. (2000). Geometry and motion. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51(4), 561–595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Belot, G., & Earman, J. (2001). Pre-socratic quantum gravity. In C. Callendar & N. Huggett (Eds.), Physics meets philosophy at the Planck scale: Contemporary theories in quantum gravity (Vol. 10, pp. 213–55). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Bennett, J. (1970). The difference between right and left. American Philosophical Quarterly, 7, 175–191. [reprinted in Van Cleve and Frederick (1991), pp. 97–130].Google Scholar
  14. Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1990). Science and necessity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Bigelow, J., Pargetter, R., & Armstrong, D. M. (1988). Quantities. Philosophical Studies, 54, 287–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Brentano, F. (1974). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. Abingdon: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. Dasgupta, S. (2013). Absolutism vs comparativism about quantity. In K. Bennett & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford Studies in Metaphysics (Vol. 8, pp. 105–147). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Dasgupta, S. (2014). On the plurality of grounds. Philosophers’ Imprint, 14(20), 1–28.Google Scholar
  19. Dasgupta, S. (2015a). Inexpressible ignorance. Philosophical Review, 124(4), 441–480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Dasgupta, S. (2015b). Substantivalism vs relationalism about space in classical physics. Philosophy Compass, 10(9), 601–624.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Dasgupta, S. (2016). Symmetry as an epistemic notion (twice over). The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67, 837–878.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Dees, M. (2018). Physical magnitudes. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 817–841.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Dennett, D. C. (1991). Real patterns. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Dijksterhuis, E. J. (1986). The mechanisation of the world picture. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  25. DiSalle, R. (2002) Space and time: Inertial frames. Stanford Encylopedia of Philosophy [revised in 2009]. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spacetime-iframes/.
  26. Dowker, F. (2008). Causal sets and the deep structure of spacetime. arXiv:gr-qc/0508109v1
  27. Earman, J. (1991). Kant, incongruous counterparts, and the nature of space and space–time. In Van Cleve and Frederick (1991), pp. 131–149. Google Scholar
  28. Eddon, M. (2013). Quantitative properties. Philosophy Compass, 8(7), 633–645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Ellis, B. (1966). Basic concepts of measurement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Esfeld, M. (2014). Quantum humeanism, or: Physicalism without properties. The Philosophical Quarterly, 64(256), 453–470.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Esfeld, M., & Deckert, D.-A. (2017). A minimalist ontology of the natural world (1st ed.). New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Esfeld, E., Deckert, D.-A., & Oldofredi, A. (2015). What is matter? The fundamental ontology of atomism and structural realism. In A. Ijjas & B. Loewer (Eds.), A guide to the philosophy of cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Esfeld, M., Lazarovici, D., Lam, V., & Hubert, M. (2017). The physics and metaphysics of primitive stuff. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 133–161.Google Scholar
  34. Field, H. (1984). Can we dispense with space-time? PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 33–90.Google Scholar
  35. Field, H. H. (1980). Science without Numbers: A defence of nominalism. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  36. Gardner, M. (1964). The new ambidextrous universe: Symmetry and asymmetry from mirror reflections to superstrings (3rd ed.). Mineola, New York: Dover Publications Inc. (revised and retitled in 1990).Google Scholar
  37. Grant, E. (1981). Physical science in the middle ages. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  38. Hall, N. (manuscript). Humean reductionism about laws of nature. http://philpapers.org/archive/HALHRA.pdf.
  39. Hubert, M. (2016). Quantity of matter or intrinsic property: Why mass cannot be both. In L. Felline, A. Ledda, F. Paoli, & E. Rossanese (Eds.), New Developments in Logic and Philosophy of Science (Vol. 3, pp. 267–77). London: College Publications.Google Scholar
  40. Huggett, N. (1999). Space from Zeno to Einstein: Classic readings with a contemporary commentary. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  41. Jammer, M. (2000). Concepts of mass in contemporary physics and philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Knox, E. (2014). Newtonian spacetime structure in light of the equivalence principle. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65(4), 863–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers, volume ii. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Lewis, D. (2009). Ramseyan humility. In D. Braddon-Mitchell & R. Nola (Eds.), Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism (pp. 203–22). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  45. Loewer, B. (1996). Humean supervenience. Philosophical Topics, 24(1), 101–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Mach, E. (1960). The science of mechanics (T. J. McCormack, Trans.). The Open Court Publishing Co. (original work published 1893).Google Scholar
  47. Martens, N. C. M. (forthcoming). The metaphysics of emergent spacetime theories. Philosophy Compass.Google Scholar
  48. Martens, N. C. M. (2017a). Against comparativism about mass in newtonian gravity—A case study in the metaphysics of scale. Ph.D. thesis, Magdalen College, University of OxfordGoogle Scholar
  49. Martens, N. C. M. (2017b). Regularity comparativism about mass in newtonian gravity. Philosophy of Science, 84(5), 1226–1238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Martens, N. C. M. (2018). Against Laplacian reduction of newtonian mass to spatiotemporal quantities. Foundations of Physics, 48(5), 591–609.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Martens, N. C. M. (2019). Machian comparativism about mass. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.  https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axz013.
  52. Maudlin, T. (1993). Buckets of water and waves of space: Why spacetime is probably a substance. Philosophy of Science, 60, 183–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Maxwell, J. C. (1873). A treatise on electricity and magnetism, vol. 1 & 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  54. Møller-Nielsen, T., & Read, J. (manuscript). Redundant epistemic symmetries.Google Scholar
  55. Mulder, H., & van de Velde-Schlick, B. (Eds.). (1979). Moritz-Schlick: Philosophical papers, volume 11-I (1909–1922) of Vienna circle collection series. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  56. Mundy, B. (1987). The metaphysics of quantity. Philosophical Studies, 51(1), 29–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Newton, I. (1686/7). Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica. London: Joseph Streater. [the Scholium to the definitions has been reprinted in Alexander (1956)].Google Scholar
  58. Perry, Z. (2016). Physical quantities: Mereology and dynamics. Ph.D. thesis. New York University.Google Scholar
  59. Pooley, O. (manuscript). The reality of spacetime.Google Scholar
  60. Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies, 2, 183–204.Google Scholar
  61. Roberts, J. T. (2016). A case for comparativism about physical quantities. https://www.academia.edu/28548115/A_Case_for_Comparativism_about_Physical_Quantities_--_SMS_2016_Geneva. Accessed September 20, 2016.
  62. Russell, B. (1903). The principles of mathematics. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
  63. Saunders, S. (2007). Mirroring as an a priori symmetry. Philosophy of Science, 74, 452–480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Schlick, M. (1922). Space and time in contemporary physics: An introduction to the theory of relativity and gravitation (H. Brose & P. Heath, Trans. from Raum und zeit in der gegenwärtigen physik, 4th edition, Berlin). See Mulder and van de Velde-Schlick (1979), ch. 9, pp. 207–269.Google Scholar
  65. Schlick, M. (1925). General theory of knowledge. Library of exact philosophy series (A. Blumberg, Trans., from the 2nd German Edition of Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, Berlin: Springer-Verlag, 1974).Google Scholar
  66. Schlick, M. (1949). Philosophy of nature (A. von Zeppelin, Trans.). Philosophy Library, Inc.Google Scholar
  67. Sider, T. (manuscript). The tools of metaphysics and the metaphysics of science. Draft of 16 August 2018.Google Scholar
  68. Skow, B. (2007). Sklar’s maneuver. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58, 777–786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Stevens, S. (2014). The dynamical approach to relativity as a form of regularity relationalism. Ph.D. thesis, University of Oxford.Google Scholar
  70. Van Cleve, J. (1991). Introduction to the arguments of 1770 and 1783. In Van Cleve and Frederick (1991), pp. 15–26.Google Scholar
  71. Van Cleve, J., & Frederick, R. E. (Eds.). (1991). The philosophy of left and right: Incongruent counterparts and the nature of space. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  72. Van Cleve, J. (1987). Right, left, and the fourth dimension. The Philosophical Review, 96, 33–68. [reprinted in Van Cleve and Frederick (1991), pp. 203–234].Google Scholar
  73. Vassallo, A., Deckert, D.-A., & Esfeld, M. (2017). Relationalism about mechanics based on a minimalist ontology of matter. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 7, 299–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Weyl, H. (1949). Philosophy of mathematics and natural science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Williams, P. (2019). Scientific realism made effective. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(1), 209–237.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Zanstra, H. (1924). A study of relative motion in connection with classical mechanics. Physical Review, 23(4), 528–545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute for Theoretical Particle Physics and CosmologyRWTH Aachen UniversityAachenGermany

Personalised recommendations