Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Time travel and counterfactual asymmetry

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We standardly evaluate counterfactuals and abilities in temporally asymmetric terms—by keeping the past fixed and holding the future open. Only future events depend counterfactually on what happens now. Past events do not. Conversely, past events are relevant to what abilities one has now in a way that future events are not. Lewis, Sider and others continue to evaluate counterfactuals and abilities in temporally asymmetric terms, even in cases of backwards time travel. I’ll argue that we need more temporally neutral methods. The past shouldn’t always be held fixed, because backwards time travel requires backwards counterfactual dependence. Future events should sometimes be held fixed, because they’re in the causal history of the past, and agents have evidence of them independently of their decisions now. We need temporally neutral methods to maintain connections between causation, counterfactuals and evidence, and if counterfactuals are used to explain the temporal asymmetry of causation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For possible scenarios, see Lewis (1976, p. 152), Smith (1997, p. 372ff.) and Sider (2002, pp. 131–133).

  2. My arguments won’t depend on the details of how abilities and counterfactuals are related. One might think that counterfactuals and abilities are only related for a subclass of counterfactuals—those relevant to abilities (Sider p. 137 n. 9). Explicitly adopting this restriction won’t change the arguments to come. Nor will it affect the point here: that context-sensitivity is what defuses the grandfather paradox.

  3. Vihvelin (1996) rejects the first reading for cases in which, she argues, the counterfactual antecedent can’t be brought about except by failure of the attempt (without introducing large miracles). Rennick (2015) rejects the first reading for cases in which the time traveller intentionally tries to bring about what they believe will not happen. I’m concerned with a broader class of cases. Moreover, my main concern at this stage is to defend the reasonableness of the ‘can’t’ reading, not to reject the possibility of the ‘can’.

  4. The apparent “coincidences” can also be explained by the system’s dynamics (Arntzenius and Maudlin 2013).

  5. Vihvelin (2011) and Rea (2015, p. 270 n. 7) also distinguish between arguments for future events limiting our freedom and fatalist arguments.

  6. Kiourti (2008, pp. 349−350) also argues that future events are relevant to an agent’s abilities when they’re in the personal past. The arguments below are more general, and do not rely on demarcating the personal past. While Rea (2015) eschews talk of counterfactuals and abilities, he also uses causal features to argue that time travellers are not free. However, Rea relies on the premise that we should keep the whole causal past of an agent fixed when evaluating what the agent is free to do at t, where the causal past includes all events that stand in the ancestral of the causal relation to events at t concerning the agent (ibid., p. 271). As Rea acknowledges (ibid., pp. 269−270), his justification for this premise relies on assuming freedom is incompatible with determinism—an assumption that I, as well as Lewis and company, would reject. I’ll argue that some future events (in the causal past) should be held fixed, not that all events in the causal past (in Rea’s sense) should be held fixed—see Sect. 5.

  7. Whether ¬B□→¬A is true depends on details of how counterfactuals are evaluated. The claim I make here is comparative: to the extent that holding past events fixed is required to rule out backtracking counterfactuals in the actual world, as in Lewis (1979) and on causal methods of evaluating counterfactuals, holding future events fixed is required to rule out backtracking in the above case.

  8. Local approaches are also difficult to square with global methods of evaluating counterfactuals like Lewis’ (1979).

  9. Lewis defines traces non-causally. However, he was wrong about the precise form and origin of the trace asymmetry (Elga 2001; Field 2003), and debate has continued over whether asymmetries of traces or ‘records’ can be explained in non-causal terms. See Reichenbach (1956), Horwich (1987, Ch. 5), Albert (2000, Ch. 6) and Loewer (2007) for attempts, and Earmam (1974) and Frisch (2010) for criticism. Earman (1974, p. 41), for example, argues that traces must be analysed in causal terms.

  10. Even if cases of backwards time travel involve causal loops, accounts still need to give direction to the causal loop. The presence of causal loops does, however, create other trouble—see Sect. 5.

  11. Lewis’ approach doesn’t actually imply that future events are held fixed. But this is due to a general problem his account has with cases of backwards time travel. Lewis’ method is global in character, seeking perfect match between largest possible spatiotemporal regions, and so has trouble capturing the local violations of causal order in cases of backwards time travel. For examples of this trouble, see Tooley (2002), Collins, Hall and Paul (2004, p. 11), and Wasserman (2015). For a related diagnosis and a causal solution, see Wasserman (2018, pp. 171–182).

  12. Ismael (2003, p. 314) and Arntzenius (2006, p. 613) also note that violations of evidential asymmetry in time travel cases may spell trouble for asymmetric counterfactual and causal reasoning. But neither takes this to affect the time traveller’s abilities. Rennick (2015) argues that a time traveller’s freedom may be limited by her beliefs. The approach I take below provides a more general route to a similar conclusion.

  13. Even so, one might hold future events fixed in virtue of the fact that they cause present events, or in virtue of the fact that they are evidenced by present events. As I discuss in the next section, these options suggests different approaches to evaluating counterfactuals.

  14. Accounts differ on whether the asymmetry of records is strict. For example, while Albert begins by drawing attention to particular methods that apparently work towards the past (and not the future) (2000, p. 113), the asymmetry he ultimately derives (ibid., p. 122) doesn’t actually entail a strict asymmetry of local records. Loewer (2007, p. 303) defines records somewhat differently, and explicitly takes the asymmetry to be matter of degree—we only have more reliable records of the past (compared to the future). For criticisms of this program, see, again, Earman (1974) and Frisch (2010).

  15. If Tim is unsure of the metaphysics of time, perhaps we’d not fault him for failing to believe his grandfather will survive—but he’d still be failing to follow his external evidence.

  16. Won’t Tim have countervailing evidence in the form of evidence about what he can do? Certain of his ability to kill the man before him, shouldn’t he be certain it isn’t his grandfather after all? (My thanks to a reviewer for the case.) In particular scenarios, one’s alethic modal evidence about what one can do (and what that would imply) may outweigh one’s epistemic modal evidence about what does happen in the actual world. (See Ismael (2017, p. 117) for more on the distinction.) What I’m committed to is a priority of epistemic modality over alethic in new settings: in these settings, modal evidence takes priority over alethic evidence in cases of conflict. My reasons for this are themselves epistemic: in new settings, we learn about what would happen if we tried only by observing what does happen when we try. So Tim shouldn’t remain certain of his ability to kill young-gramps and take this to throw in doubt his evidence of young-gramps’ identity.

  17. There are difficult issues to explore concerning what it is for Tim to ‘have’ evidence. For example, does Tim have evidence when he has an envelope that (unbeknownst to him) contains relevant information, but has, a) left it behind, unopened, or b) brought it with him, unopened, or c) brought it with him and read it? (My thanks to a reviewer for the case.) My responses are: a) no, b) probably not, c) yes. The answers (to my mind) turn on what we take the relevant epistemic standards of a world to be (noting that these may be different from standards of praise or blame). I suspect someone isn’t necessarily failing as an epistemic agent when they don’t open letters, but they are if they fail to take into account information contained in letters they’ve read. But one could argue for different standards, or take a non-normative approach.

  18. Differences may also arise due to how fine-grained the relata are, or how probabilistic relations are treated.

  19. There may also be events evidenced in the present that aren’t in the causal past, and events in the causal past that aren’t evidenced in the present. So holding evidenced events fixed is, again, not equivalent to holding the casual past fixed.

  20. Horacek (2005, p. 424), however, argues that we should hold the past fixed when determining chances.

  21. Arntzenius and Maudlin (2013) discuss independent problems concerning indeterminacy.

  22. Rea (2015, pp. 273–274) also notes this concern with respect to what we are free to do. Rea prefers to keep the causal past fixed in a very wide sense. But his justification for doing so is an incompatibilist one.

  23. What would happen were old-Coleridge not to teach the poem to his younger-self depends on details of the case. If Coleridge’s evidence of knowing the poem is had independently of his evidence of how he came to learn it, his knowing the poem is held fixed—he will come to learn the poem by some other means. Otherwise, his knowing it is not held fixed.

References

  • Albert, D. Z. (2000). Time and chance. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arntzenius, F. (2006). Time travel: Double your fun. Philosophy Compass, 1(6), 599–616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arntzenius, F., & Maudlin, T. (2013). Time travel and modern physics. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2013/entries/time-travel-phys/. Accessed October 24, 2016.

  • Carroll, J. W. (2010). Context, conditionals, fatalism, time travel, and freedom. In J. K. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & H. S. Silverstein (Eds.), Time and identity (pp. 79–93). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, J., Hall, N., & Paul, L. A. (2004). Counterfactuals and causation: History, problems, and prospects. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 1–57). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, P. R. (2014). Lewisian time travel in a relativistic setting. Metaphysica, 15(2), 329–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (1974). An attempt to add a little direction to “the problem of the direction of time”. Philosophy of Science, 41(1), 15–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (2004). Counterfactuals and the benefit of hindsight. In P. Dowe & P. Noordhof (Eds.), Cause and chance: Causation in an indeterministic world (pp. 12–27). Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2001). Statistical mechanics and the asymmetry of counterfactual dependence. Philosophy of Science, 68(3), S313–S324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernandes, A. Forth. Freedom, self-prediction, and the possibility of time travel. Philosophical Studies.

  • Fernandes, A. (2016). Varieties of epistemic freedom. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(4), 736–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernandes, A. (2017). A deliberative approach to causation. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 95(3), 686–708.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2003). Causation in a physical world. In M. J. Loux & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 435–460). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (2010). Does a low-entropy constraint prevent us from influencing the past? In G. Ernst & A. Hüttemann (Eds.), Time, chance and reduction: philosophical aspects of statistical mechanics (pp. 13–33). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Halpern, J. (2000). Axiomatizing causal reasoning. Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research, 12, 317–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hiddleston, E. (2005). A causal theory of counterfactuals. Noûs, 39(4), 632–657.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). The intransitivity of causation revealed in equations and graphs. Journal of Philosophy, 98(6), 273–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horacek, D. (2005). Time travel in indeterministic worlds. The Monist, 88(3), 423–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1987). Asymmetries in time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2003). Closed causal loops and the bilking argument. Synthese, 136(3), 305–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ismael, J. (2017). An Empiricist’s guide to objective modality. In M. Slater & Z. Yudell (Eds.), Metaphysics and the philosophy of science: New essays (pp. 109–125). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1977). A causal theory of counterfactuals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 55(1), 3–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiourti, I. (2008). Killing baby Suzy. Philosophical Studies, 139(3), 343–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kvart, I. (1986). A theory of counterfactuals. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation. The Journal of Philosophy, 70(17), 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1976). The paradoxes of time travel. American Philosophical Quarterly, 13(2), 145–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Counterfactual dependence and time’s arrow. Noûs, 13(4), 455–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1981). Are we free to break the laws? Theoria, 47(3), 113–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (2007). Counterfactuals and the second law. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality (pp. 293–326). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. (2015). Time travelers are not free. Journal of Philosophy, 112(5), 266–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, Hans. (1956). The direction of time. In M. Reichenbach (Ed.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

  • Rennick, S. (2015). Things mere mortals can do, but philosophers can’t. Analysis, 75(1), 22–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rice, H. (2015). Fatalism. In E. N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/fatalism. Accessed 24 November, 2016.

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). Counterfactuals, causal independence and conceptual circularity. Analysis, 64(4), 299–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2002). Time travel, coincidences and counterfactuals. Philosophical Studies, 110(2), 115–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smeenk, C., & Wüthrich, C. (2011). Time travel and time machines. In C. Callender (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of time (pp. 577–630). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. J. J. (1997). Bananas enough for time travel? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48(3), 363–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (2002). Backward causation and the Stalnaker–Lewis approach to counterfactuals. Analysis, 62(3), 191–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. (1996). What time travelers cannot do. Philosophical Studies, 81(2/3), 315–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vihvelin, K. 2011. Two objections to the possibility of time travel. http://vihvelin.typepad.com/vihvelincom/2011/05/two-objecti/. Accessed April 28, 2016.

  • Wasserman, R. (2015). Lewis on backward causation. Thought, 4, 141–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman, R. (2018). Paradoxes of time travel. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

My warm thanks to the following people for helpful comments, discussions and suggestions: David Albert, Kristie Miller, Achille Varzi, Carolina Sartorio, Alasdair Richmond, Jenann Ismael, Anjan Chakravartty, Matthew Brown, Kareem Khalifa, Yann Benétreau-Dupin, Edouard Machery, Jonathan Tallant, Christian Loew, Juliusz Doboszewski, and Giuliano Torrengo. This work was supported by a Postdoctoral Fellowship at the Center for Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, and a Research Fellowship on the AHRC project ‘Time: Between Metaphysics and Psychology’ at the University of Warwick (AH/P00217X/1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alison Fernandes.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fernandes, A. Time travel and counterfactual asymmetry. Synthese 198, 1983–2001 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02186-w

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02186-w

Keywords

Navigation