Springer Nature is making Coronavirus research free. View research | View latest news | Sign up for updates

World enough and form: why cosmology needs hylomorphism

Abstract

This essay proposes a comprehensive blueprint for the hylomorphic foundations of cosmology. The key philosophical explananda in cosmology are those dealing with global processes and structures, the regularity of global regularities, and the existence of the global as such. The possibility of elucidating these using alternatives to hylomorphism is outlined and difficulties with these alternatives are raised. Hylomorphism, by contrast, provides a sound philosophical ground for cosmology insofar as it leads to notions of cosmic essence, the unity of complex essences, and globally emergent properties. These are used as the basis to account for the aforementioned cosmological explananda and to resolve two problems in the philosophy of cosmology: the meta-law dilemma and the uniqueness of the universe. In summary, cosmology needs hylomorphism because it is able to ground cosmology’s efforts as a scientific inquiry. It can do so because hylomorphism philosophically accounts for changing substances and aggregates of substances, the various scales of law-governed behavior measured by the natures of those substances, and how those substances as parts relate to the universe as a whole.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

Notes

  1. 1.

    Contra Dingle (1937) and Hawking and Mlodinow (2012).

  2. 2.

    See Rovelli (2018) for a general defense of this idea, and Ellis (2014) for specific defense.

  3. 3.

    See McMullin (1981), and his (1969) is a review of all possible philosophies of nature (Gale and Urani 1993; Leslie 1999; Heller 2011; Ellis 2006, 2014, 2017; Unger and Smolin 2014, p. xvii).

  4. 4.

    We would thus distinguish “philosophy of nature” from “metaphysics” or “first philosophy,” as did Aristotle (see Metaphysics, VI.1, 1026a27–32), although such epistemological bookkeeping need not be accepted by readers in order to follow or accept our arguments.

  5. 5.

    See Tahko (2017); Oderberg (2017, p. 218).

  6. 6.

    Exceptions at the microscopic scale usually include unicellular organism and free atoms, although the latter are debated by hylomorphists as instances of substances in their own right.

  7. 7.

    For recent work on this philosophy of the “middle-sized” or “ordinary” object; see Thomasson (2007), Van Brakel (2013), Boulter (2013) and Needham (2017).

  8. 8.

    The literature on hylomorphism is vast; for the general background to our approach, consider Maritain (1940, 1951, 1995), De Koninck (1959, 1961, 1964, 2008, 2009) and Wallace (1996). Brague (2015, p. 37), expresses our concern: “I take here the word ‘cosmology’ in the meaning that is suggested by its etymology: a logos about the kosmos. Not a description, but some sort of account, an attempt at making sense of it, at deciphering its meaning.”

  9. 9.

    On the schema itself, see Aristotle (2014), Posterior Analytics, I.6, 75a29–37, Aquinas (1958, 1989), Maritain (1951) and De Koninck (1957). To fill out this schema, we consulted Whitrow (1959), Tolman (1987), Harrison (2000), Hawley and Holcomb (2005), and Ellis (2006, 2014, 2017).

  10. 10.

    See Aquinas (1886), In De Caelo, lib. 1, lect. 1, nn. 4–5.

  11. 11.

    Note that Ellis uses “object” here in a way that it names the “subject” of cosmology. An object of our experience can also be the subject of an inquiry.

  12. 12.

    Compare Pruss (2013, pp. 120–121, 132). We further clarify “grounding” in Sect. 2.

  13. 13.

    Another issue that we do not have space to consider in this essay is the question of how mathematics is applicable to the study of nature. However, see the final argument in Sect. 4.2.

  14. 14.

    See Bondi (1990, p. 192), Gale (2017) and Barrow and Tipler (1988, pp. 255–256).

  15. 15.

    See Ellis (2011, 2014), Kragh (2009) and Stoeger et al. (2004).

  16. 16.

    See Oderberg (2009) for a convincing critique.

  17. 17.

    The Everettian thesis does not add anything new to cosmological multiverses as such, but merely extends existing ones into various quantum branches (Tegmark 2003).

  18. 18.

    See Ellis (2014) and Unger and Smolin (2014, Part I, ch. 1, and Part II, ch. 2).

  19. 19.

    One subsequently asks, qua cosmologist, how a multi-domain model is testable.

  20. 20.

    By using this schema we not only gain a broader view of possible alternatives but can usefully juxtapose contemporary views with older traditions. While Aristotle’s schema does not, in places, map neatly onto contemporary ideas, reviving his division and seeing its plausibility will complement our revival and defense of the division’s original theoretical target: hylomorphism. Besides, the usefulness of returning to the Greeks for inspiration has been noted before: “In probing the foundations of any domain of contemporary problems—e.g., of physics—one discovers the same structures that the Greek philosophers discovered long ago, if from a different angle” (von Weizsäcker 2014, p. 136).

  21. 21.

    See Heil (2017), Dumsday (2012), Bird (2007, pp. vii, 97) and Feser (2014, pp. 69–70).

  22. 22.

    See Lewis (1983, 1987, 1994, 2001) [1973].

  23. 23.

    See Harré and Madden (1975), Dumsday (2012); French (2014, p. 232) and Simpson et al. (2017, p. 125).

  24. 24.

    Prominent proponents include Roger Penrose or George Ellis.

  25. 25.

    See Dretske (1977) and Tooley (1977). Armstrong (1983, 1997), claims to avoid the charge of Platonism; see Carroll (1994, Appendix A), Dumsday (2013, p. 143) and Mumford (2004, p. 91); at least Bird (2007, pp. 51–55), and Feser (2014, p. 70), characterize Armstrong’s view about universals as closer to the Aristotelian line. However, insofar as they all fall prey to the third-man objection leveled against Platonism, based upon second-order universals, we consider these views together.

  26. 26.

    As a basis for the ontological interpretation of relativity theory and thus a possible philosophical ground for cosmology, OSR is critiqued—effectively, in our view—by Feser (2017, pp. 47–50). However, since Feser limits himself to special relativity, his critique is also limited. We also must leave aside OSR in this essay, since we do not have the space to do it justice.

  27. 27.

    See Armstrong (1983, pp. 85–86).

  28. 28.

    Similar points are made by Bird (2007, pp. vii, 47), and see especially Heil (2017).

  29. 29.

    See Harré and Madden (1975, p. 80).

  30. 30.

    See Plato, Parmenides 132a–b; Aristotle, Metaphysics 990b15, 1059b5–10. Hence, the problem is generalizable to other versions of Platonism. The other key difficulty is Mumford’s “Central Dilemma”; see Mumford (2004, pp. 143–145) and Dumsday (2012, p. 116).

  31. 31.

    Bird (2007, p. 94).

  32. 32.

    See Groff and Greco (2013, p. 3); see also French (2014, p. 248ff).

  33. 33.

    In particular, the hylomorphist must address concerns of dispositional monism (Bird 2007) or other versions of hylomorphism; for such replies, see Oderberg (2011, 2013), and Koons (2014).

  34. 34.

    Koons (2018a) helpfully discusses the last three issues.

  35. 35.

    See Parmenides, Fragment DK B2.

  36. 36.

    To this a Heraclitean would agree, but object to any implied permanence of those individuals.

  37. 37.

    It would also be granted by Heraclitus, who posits a logos to the flux of being.

  38. 38.

    Here the Heraclitean parts company with us; however, see Aristotle, Metaphysics IV.3–4 and Plato (1997), Cratylus, 439c–440e and 439d on the various problems that result. See Aertsen (1987, pp. 16–31), on the medieval notion of the katallel structure of being, summarized in lapidary fashion by Aquinas (1884), In Phys., III. 5, n. 15: “The modes of being are proportional to the modes of predicating.” (Translations of Aquinas our own unless indicated.).

  39. 39.

    See De Koninck (2008, p. 259).

  40. 40.

    Ibid.

  41. 41.

    The following line of argument follows De Koninck (2008, pp. 259–261).

  42. 42.

    See also Oderberg (2017), Dumsday (2010) and Gorman (2014).

  43. 43.

    See Aquinas (1884), In Phys., lib. 2, lect. 1, n. 5: “[Aristotle] adds primarily [to the definition of nature] because nature, even as it is a principle of the motion of composite things, it is not such first. Thus, that an animal falls down is not due to the nature of the animal as such, but due to the nature of the predominant element.”.

  44. 44.

    See Larenz (2013, pp. 495–496).

  45. 45.

    This view claims that one substance has only one substantial form, not many. For various defenses, see Aquinas (1888, ST, Ia, q. 76, a. 4; 1918, ScG, II.58); also Feser (2014, p. 187ff).

  46. 46.

    However, the hylomorphist must have distinct views about the details; see fns. 48, 49.

  47. 47.

    Aquinas (1888, ST, Ia, q. 45, a. 7, c. (emphasis ours)). According to Aquinas, this relationship between forms eventually constitutes the form of the universe as a whole, including quotidian cases: “A mouse is killed by a cat to preserve the good of the universe. For this is the order of the universe, that one animal lives off another” (Aquinas 2018, Super Mat., X, lect. 2, n. 874).

  48. 48.

    As critics and proponents of dispositionalism have noted, conservations laws “deserve special attention and, in any case, extra work is needed for their accommodation within the context of [dispositionalism]” (Livanios 2018, p. 70; see also Ellis 2001, pp. 205, 249; Bird 2007, pp. 213–215; Katzav 2005; Smart and Thébault 2015). Since GEP permits the local ontology of hylomorphic substances to be determinable in part by global conditions, conservations principles as features of the coordinated interactivity of physical objects in the cosmos can be accommodated. We plan a separate defense to show in detail how hylomorphism meshes with least action and conservation principles.

  49. 49.

    A development of the hylomorphic account of the physical continuum, the continuity of motion, and its implications for endurantism and perdurantism is beyond the scope of this essay; on this Aristotelian theory of the continuum, see Hassing (1991), White (1992), and Hellman and Shapiro (2018).

  50. 50.

    We note below where our hylomorphic account must be articulated with more precision so as to incorporate, into a broadly Neo-Aristotelian framework, the various foundational concepts and current difficulties of classical, relativistic, and quantum mechanics. Regarding the epistemological requirements of this framework, see Cartwright (1989, 1999), and Lanao and Teh 2017. Cartwright (1989, pp. 198–199) acknowledges the “traditional metaphysical issues” related to abstraction and the problem of universals at play here; in this respect it is useful to consider whether older theories of abstraction can apply in these contemporary contexts; see Maritain 1995, De Koninck 1957, and Brungardt 2016, 2018.

  51. 51.

    De Koninck (2008, pp. 377–378).

  52. 52.

    Hylomorphism at the quantum scale presents unique challenges. Given the scale of application of hylomorphism that we are focusing on, we must prescind from, while acknowledging, the difficulties that the hylomorphic model faces when dealing with the synchronic structure of substances at microscopic, quantum scales. These difficulties are active areas of research among hylomorphists of different schools (e.g., consider Koons 2018b). Our proposals of CE, UCE, and GEP do not require specific conclusions about the hylomorphism of quantum physics, although it does imply a specific approach, viz., that “ordinary objects” at the mesoscopic scale (e.g., human beings, animals) be taken as paradigmatic instances of substances. We follow Eddington (1933, p. 37): “The twoness of two electrons is not completely like the twoness of two apples.” Quantum non-locality also poses an as-yet unmet challenge to hylomorphism as a “local” ontology of substances unable to act at a distance. Yet substantial form is not “localized” by spacetime points (which are “local” in a mathematical sense); rather, substantial form is ontologically prior to space and time. Various hylomorphic proposals include Wallace (1979, 1996), Smith (1999) and Simpson et al. (2017). See also Kastner et al. (2018).

  53. 53.

    Maritain (1995), De Koninck (1957); see also Franklin (2014) for a generally Aristotelian approach. This view proposes a theory of mixed or subalternate sciences which claims that mathematical principles stand as form to the matter of natural scientific considerations; see Aquinas (1958) and Mullahy (1946). It would require a longer excursion to examine how the manner of conceiving things and (recursively) conceiving concepts influences the foundations of modern mathematics and its physical applications, in this case, regarding the nature of spacetime. Such a conceptual “desedimentation” regarding mathematics is undertaken by Klein (1992), and see Hassing (2017); Klein’s approach is applied to the ontology of spacetime by Cosgrove (2018). Hylomorphic and dispositionalist accounts of spacetime have been proposed: see Feser (2017) and Bird (2017). The theoretical cost adopting a privileged present, contrary to the demands of relativity, is absorbed by Unger and Smolin (2014) (see pp. 183–184, pp. 386–88) by appealing to a “shape dynamics” approach to gravity, one that recovers relativistic mechanics while maintaining a privileged present; see Mercati (2018) for more. It is unclear whether the same theoretical escape route is available to hylomorphism, which typically also defends a type of presentism.

  54. 54.

    Larenz (2013, pp. 496–497).

  55. 55.

    Some unknown factor prevents quantum vacuum energy in the universe from attaining its predicted value that is 10120greater than the observed one, yet that unknown does not eliminate effects of dark energy at global scales (see Peebles and Ratra 2003, pp. 561–562).

  56. 56.

    We grant for the sake of argument that the universe does exhibit law-regime changes.

  57. 57.

    Unger and Smolin (2014, p. 27, and see pp. 245, 301 n).

  58. 58.

    A position akin to Armstrong’s could appeal to higher-order universal relations, however, see Lange (2008) against this; the discussions of Armstrong (1983, pp. 22–23), and Lange (2008, pp. 88–90), suggest that the regularity view of laws could not avoid the meta-law dilemma.

  59. 59.

    Some cosmologists recognize that there are such arguments proper to natural philosophy in this sense (Unger and Smolin 2014), or at any rate arguments that are closer to the sciences on this topic (Ellis 2014, pp. 11–13).

  60. 60.

    See also Juarez (2017) for a similar argument.

  61. 61.

    Compare Aristotle, De Caelo I.9.

  62. 62.

    Aristotle also argues from the causal and physical-topological unity of the universe to its numerical unity (see De Caelo I.8); however, his universe’s topology lacked extensive symmetries (it had one spherical boundary with one center); see Jammer (1993, pp. 219–221) and Earman (1989). However, the spirit of his argument seems sound.

  63. 63.

    This is echoed by many critiques of the multiverse (para-universe) hypothesis; for instance, see Ellis and Silk (2014).

  64. 64.

    Aquinas (1886), In De Caelo, lib. 1, lect. 1, n. 2.

  65. 65.

    See Aquinas (1918), ScG, II.39: “The form of the universe consists in the distinction and order of its parts.” These “parts” are primarily kinds and secondarily individuals; see Blanchette (1992).

  66. 66.

    For instance, see Prigogine and Stengers (1984), Chaisson (2001, 2005), Novo Villaverde et al. (2018), Maritain (1997) and De Koninck (2008).

  67. 67.

    See De Koninck (2008, pp. 284, 297–298, 314), Dumsday (2011) and Koons (2018b, p. 162).

  68. 68.

    See Aquinas (1884), In De Caelo, lib. 1, lect. 19, n. 197. Aquinas argues that the uniqueness of the world could be inferred from the oneness of its First Mover; he argues that its uniqueness follows from its unified order to the First Mover as an end; he argues that, even were God able to make para-universes, this would either be contrary to his wisdom (if they were wholly alike) or the complete set of such universes would itself be the universe (if they each exhibited diverse perfections); and he argues that the essence of the world and its goodness is “more powerful” in its own kind by being one and not many in number.

  69. 69.

    Just such a theistic “quasi-deduction”—the name is from Geiger (1953, p. 397, n).—of the universe from the nature of divine causality is proposed by Aquinas (1926, ScG, III.97).

  70. 70.

    Consider Peterson (1996), Dumsday (2012) and Beltrán (2001, 2016).

References

  1. Aertsen, J. (1987). Nature and creature: Thomas Aquinas’s way of thought. Leiden: BRILL.

  2. Aquinas, S. T. (1884). Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 2: Commentaria in octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis (Vols. 1–50, Vol. 2). Romae: Ex Typographia Polyglotta S. C. de Propaganda Fide.

  3. Aquinas, S. T. (1886). Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 3: In libros Aristotelis De caelo et mundo expositio; In librum primum Aristotelis De generatione et corruptione expositio (Vols. 1–50, Vol. 3). Romae: Ex Typographia Polyglotta S. C. de Propaganda Fide.

  4. Aquinas, S. T. (1888). Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 4: Pars prima Summae theologiae qq. 1-49 (Vols. 1–50, Vol. 4). Romae: Ex Typographia Polyglotta S. C. de Propaganda Fide.

  5. Aquinas, S. T. (1918). Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 13: Summa contra gentiles (libri primus et secundus) cum commentariis Francisci de Sylvestris Ferrariensis. Romae: Typis Riccardi Garroni.

  6. Aquinas, S. T. (1926). Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 14: Summa contra gentiles (liber tertius) cum commentariis Francisci de Sylvestris Ferrariensis. Romae: Typis Riccardi Garroni.

  7. Aquinas, S. T. (1958). The division and methods and the sciences: Questions V and VI of his commentary on the “De Trinitate” of Boethius (A. Maurer, Trans.) (2nd ed.). Toronto: The Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.

  8. Aquinas, S. T. (1989). Opera omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita, t. 1*/2: Expositio libri Posteriorum (2nd ed., Vols. 1–50, Vol. 1*/2). Roma-Paris: Commissio Leonina-J. Vrin.

  9. Aquinas, S. T. (2018). Super evangelium S. Matthaei lectura. Lander: Aquinas Institute for the Study of Sacred Doctrine. https://aquinas.cc/180/182/~2580. Accessed January 22, 2018.

  10. Aristotle. (2004). Physics, or natural hearing (G. Coughlin, Trans.). South Bend, IN: St. Augustine’s Press.

  11. Aristotle. (2014). The complete works of Aristotle: The revised Oxford translation, one-volume digital edition (J. Barnes, Ed.). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  12. Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  13. Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  14. Barrow, J. D., & Tipler, F. J. (1988). The anthropic cosmological principle. New York: Oxford University Press.

  15. Beltrán, O. (2001). El principio antrópico y la interpretación teleológica del universo. Teología, 78(2), 169–208.

  16. Beltrán, O. (2016). Principio antrópico. In C. E. Vanney, I. Silva, & J. F. Franck (Eds.), Diccionario Interdisciplinar Austral. http://dia.austral.edu.ar/Principio_antrópico. Accessed November 21, 2018.

  17. Bigelow, J., Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1992). The world as one of a kind: Natural necessity and laws of nature. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43(3), 371–388.

  18. Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  19. Bird, A. (2017). Manifesting time and space: Background-free physical theories. In J. D. Jacobs (Ed.), Causal powers (pp. 127–138). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  20. Blanchette, O. (1992). The perfection of the universe according to Aquinas: A teleological cosmology. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University.

  21. Bondi, H. (1990). The cosmological scene 1945–1952. In B. Bertotti, R. Balbinot, S. Bergia, & A. Messina (Eds.), Modern cosmology in retrospect (pp. 189–196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  22. Boulter, S. (2013). Metaphysics from a biological point of view. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

  23. Brague, R. (2015). On the need for a philosophy of nature and on Aquinas’s help in sketching one. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 89, 35–43.

  24. Brungardt, J. G. (2016). Charles De Koninck and the sapiential character of natural philosophy. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 90(1), 1–24.

  25. Brungardt, J. G. (2018). St. Thomas and modern natural science: Reconsidering abstraction from matter. In C. A. Casanova G & I. S. del Pozo (Eds.), Cognoscens in Actu Est Ipsum Cognitum in Actu: Sobre Los Tipos y Grados de Conocimiento (pp. 433–471). Santiago: RIL Editores.

  26. Butterfield, J. (2006a). The rotating discs argument defeated. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(1), 1–45.

  27. Butterfield, J. N. (2006b). Against pointillisme about geometry. In F. Stadler & M. Stöltzner (Eds.), Time and history: Proceedings of the 28th international Ludwig Wittgenstein symposium, Kirchberg am Wechsel, Austria 2005 (pp. 181–222). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

  28. Butterfield, J. (2006c). Against pointillisme about mechanics. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(4), 709–753.

  29. Butterfield, J. (2011). Against pointillisme: A call to arms. In D. Dieks, W. J. Gonzalez, S. Hartmann, T. Uebel, & M. Weber (Eds.), Explanation, prediction, and confirmation (pp. 347–365). Netherlands: Springer.

  30. Carroll, J. W. (1994). Laws of nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  31. Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  32. Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  33. Chaisson, E. J. (2001). Cosmic evolution: The rise of complexity in nature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  34. Chaisson, E. J. (2005). Epic of evolution: Seven ages of the cosmos. New York: Columbia University Press.

  35. Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  36. Clarke, W. N. (2009). System: A new category of being? In The creative retrieval of Saint Thomas Aquinas: Essays in Thomistic philosophy, new and old (pp. 39–47). New York: Fordham University Press.

  37. Cosgrove, J. K. (2018). Relativity without spacetime. New York, NY: Springer.

  38. De Koninck, C. (1957). Abstraction from matter (I): Notes on St. Thomas’s prologue to the Physics. Laval théologique et philosophique, 13(2), 133–196.

  39. De Koninck, C. (1959). Natural science as philosophy. Culture, 20(3), 245–267.

  40. De Koninck, C. (1961). The unity and diversity of natural science. In V. E. Smith (Ed.), The philosophy of physics (pp. 5–24). New York: St. John’s University Press.

  41. De Koninck, C. (1964). The hollow universe. Québec: Presses de l’Université Laval.

  42. De Koninck, C. (2008). The writings of Charles De Koninck: Volume one (R. McInerny, Ed. & Trans.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

  43. De Koninck, C. (2009). The writings of Charles De Koninck: Volume two (R. McInerny, Ed. & Trans.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

  44. Dingle, H. (1937). Modern aristotelianism. Nature, 139, 784–786.

  45. Dretske, F. I. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44(2), 248–268.

  46. Dumsday, T. (2010). Natural kinds and the problem of complex essences. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 88(4), 619–634.

  47. Dumsday, T. (2011). Why Thomistic philosophy of nature implies (something like) Big-Bang cosmology. Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association, 85, 69–78.

  48. Dumsday, T. (2012). Have the laws of nature been eliminated? In G. Butera (Ed.), Reading the cosmos: Nature, science, and wisdom (pp. 111–128). Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.

  49. Dumsday, T. (2013). Laws of nature don’t have ceteris paribus clauses, they are ceteris paribus clauses. Ratio, 26(2), 134–147.

  50. Earman, J. (1989). World enough and space-time: Absolute vs. relational theories of space and time. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  51. Eddington, S. A. S. (1933). Physics and philosophy. Philosophy, 8(29), 30–43.

  52. Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  53. Ellis, B. (2002). Philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

  54. Ellis, B. (2005). Katzav on the limitations of dispositionalism. Analysis, 65(1), 90–92.

  55. Ellis, G. F. R. (2006). Issues in the philosophy of cosmology. In J. Butterfield & J. Earman (Eds.), Philosophy of physics (Handbook of the philosophy of science) (pp. 1183–1284). Amsterdam: North Holland.

  56. Ellis, G. F. R. (2011). Does the multiverse really exist? Scientific American, 305(2), 38–43.

  57. Ellis, G. F. R. (2014). On the philosophy of cosmology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 46, 5–23.

  58. Ellis, G. F. R. (2016). How can physics underlie the mind? Top-down causation in the human context. Berlin: Springer.

  59. Ellis, G. F. R. (2017). The domain of cosmology and the testing of cosmological theories. In K. Chamcham, J. Silk, J. D. Barrow, & S. Saunders (Eds.), The philosophy of cosmology (pp. 3–39). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  60. Ellis, G. F. R., Kirchner, U., & Stoeger, W. R. (2004). Multiverses and physical cosmology. Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society, 347(3), 921–936.

  61. Ellis, G. F. R., & Silk, J. (2014). Scientific method: Defend the integrity of physics. Nature, 516, 321–323.

  62. Feser, E. (2014). Scholastic metaphysics: A contemporary introduction. Neunkirchen-Seelscheid: Editiones Scholasticae.

  63. Feser, E. (2017). Actuality, potentiality, and relativity’s block universe. In W. M. R. Simpson, R. C. Koons & N. J. Teh (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian perspectives on contemporary science (pp. 35–60). New York: Routledge.

  64. Franklin, J. (2014). An Aristotelian realist philosophy of mathematics: Mathematics as the science of quantity and structure. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

  65. French, S. (2014). The structure of the world: Metaphysics and representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  66. Gale, G. (2017). Cosmology: Methodological debates in the 1930s and 1940s. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2017). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/cosmology-30s/. Accessed November 21, 2018.

  67. Gale, G., & Urani, J. (1993). Philosophical midwifery and the birthpangs of modern cosmology. American Journal of Physics, 61(1), 66–73.

  68. Geiger, O. P. (1953). La participation dans la philosophie de S. Thomas d’Aquin (2nd ed.). Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin.

  69. Gorman, M. (2014). Essentiality as foundationality. In D. D. Novotný & L. Novák (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian perspectives in metaphysics (pp. 119–137). New York: Routledge.

  70. Groff, R., & Greco, J. (Eds.). (2013). Powers and capacities in philosophy: The new Aristotelianism. New York: Routledge.

  71. Guth, A., & Steinhardt, P. J. (1984). The inflationary universe. Scientific American, 250(5), 116–128.

  72. Harré, R., & Madden, E. H. (1975). Causal powers: A theory of natural necessity. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.

  73. Harrison, E. (2000). Cosmology: The science of the universe (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  74. Hassing, R. F. (1991). Thomas Aquinas on Physics VII.1 and the Aristotelian science of the physical continuum. In D. O. Dahlstrom (Ed.), Nature and scientific method (Vol. 22, pp. 127–157). Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.

  75. Hassing, R. F. (2017). Modern turns in mathematics and physics. In M. Rohlf (Ed.), The modern turn (Vol. 60, pp. 131–182). Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.

  76. Hawking, S., & Mlodinow, L. (2012). The grand design. New York: Bantam.

  77. Hawley, J. F., & Holcomb, K. A. (2005). Foundations of modern cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  78. Heil, J. (2017). Real modalities. In J. D. Jacobs (Ed.), Causal powers (pp. 90–104). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  79. Heller, M. (2011). Philosophy in science: An historical introduction. Dordrecht: Springer.

  80. Hellman, G., & Shapiro, S. (2018). Varieties of continua: From regions to points and back. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  81. Jammer, M. (1993). Concepts of space: The history of theories of space in physics (3rd ed.). New York: Dover Publications.

  82. Juarez, P. (2017). From the unity of the world to God: A teleo-cosmological argument for God’s existence. Scientia et Fides, 5(2), 1–21.

  83. Kastner, R. E., Kauffman, S., & Epperson, M. (2018). Taking Heisenberg’s potentia seriously. International Journal of Quantum Foundations, 4(2), 158–172.

  84. Katzav, J. (2005). Ellis on the limitations of dispositionalism. Analysis, 65(1), 92–94.

  85. Klein, J. (1992). Greek mathematical thought and the origin of algebra. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.

  86. Koons, R. C. (2014). Staunch vs. faint-hearted hylomorphism: Toward an Aristotelian account of composition. Res Philosophica, 91, 1–27.

  87. Koons, R. C. (2018a). Forms as simple and individual grounds of things’ natures. Metaphysics, 1(1), 1–11.

  88. Koons, R. C. (2018b). Hylomorphic escalation: An Aristotelian interpretation of quantum thermodynamics and chemistry. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 92(1), 159–178.

  89. Kragh, H. (2009). Contemporary history of cosmology and the controversy over the multiverse. Annals of Science, 66(4), 529–551.

  90. Lanao, X., & Teh, N. J. (2017). Dodging the Fundamentalist Threat. In W. M. R. Simpson, R. C. Koons, & N. J. Teh (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian perspectives on contemporary science (pp. 15–34). New York: Routledge.

  91. Lange, M. (2008). Could the laws of nature change? Philosophy of Science, 75(1), 69–92.

  92. Larenz, R. (2013). What can Thomistic philosophy of nature contribute to physics? Societal Studies, 5(2), 481–500.

  93. Leslie, J. (Ed.). (1999). Modern cosmology & philosophy. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

  94. Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61(4), 343–377.

  95. Lewis, D. (1987). Philosophical papers (Vol. II). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  96. Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103(412), 473–490.

  97. Lewis, D. K. (2001). Counterfactuals (reprint ed.). Malden, MA: Wiley.

  98. Livanios, V. (2018). Hamilton’s principle and dispositional essentialism: Friends or foes? Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 49(1), 59–71.

  99. Maritain, J. (1940). Science and wisdom. London: G. Bles, Scribner.

  100. Maritain, J. (1951). Philosophy of nature. New York: Philosophical Library.

  101. Maritain, J. (1995). Distinguish to unite, or, the degrees of knowledge (G. B. Phelan, Trans., R. M. McInerny, Ed.) (The collected works of Jacques Maritain, vol. 7). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

  102. Maritain, J. (1997). Towards a Thomist idea of evolution. In R. M. McInerny, F. Crosson, & B. Doering (Eds.), B. Doering (Trans.), Untrammeled approaches (The collected works of Jacques Maritain, vol. 20, pp. 85–131). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

  103. McCoy, C. D. (2018). On classical motion. Philosopher’s Imprint, 18(9). http://hdl.handle.net/2027/spo.3521354.0018.009. Accessed November 17, 2018.

  104. McMullin, E. (1969). Philosophies of nature. The New Scholasticism, 43(1), 29–74.

  105. McMullin, E. (1981). Is philosophy relevant to cosmology? American Philosophical Quarterly, 18(3), 177–189.

  106. Mercati, F. (2018). Shape dynamics: Relativity and relationalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  107. Mullahy, B. (1946). Subalternation and mathematical physics. Laval théologique et philosophique, 2(2), 89–107.

  108. Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.

  109. Needham, P. (2017). Macroscopic metaphysics: Middle-sized objects and longish processes. Cham: Springer.

  110. Novo Villaverde, F. J., Pereda, R., & Sánchez Cañizares, J. (2018). Naturaleza creativa. Madrid: Rialp.

  111. Oderberg, D. S. (2009). Real essentialism. London: Routledge.

  112. Oderberg, D. S. (2011). The world is not an asymmetric graph. Analysis, 71(1), 3–10.

  113. Oderberg, D. S. (2013). No potency without actuality: The case of graph theory. In T. E. Tahko (Ed.), Contemporary aristotelian metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  114. Oderberg, D. S. (2017). The great unifier: Form and the unity of the organism. In W. M. R. Simpson, R. C. Koons & N. J. Teh (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian perspectives on contemporary science (pp. 211–232). New York: Routledge.

  115. Peebles, P. J. E., & Ratra, B. (2003). The cosmological constant and dark energy. Reviews of Modern Physics, 75(2), 559–606.

  116. Peterson, J. (1996). Law and thomistic exemplarism. The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review, 60(1), 81–108.

  117. Plato. (1997). Plato: Complete works (J. M. Cooper & D. S. Hutchinson, Eds.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

  118. Prigogine, I., & Stengers, I. (1984). Order out of chaos: Man’s new dialogue with nature. Toronto: Bantam Books.

  119. Pruss, A. R. (2013). Aristotelian forms and laws of nature. Analiza i Egzystencja, 24, 115–132.

  120. Rovelli, C. (2018). Physics needs philosophy. Philosophy needs physics. Foundations of Physics, 48(5), 481–491.

  121. Schaffer, J. (2009). Spacetime the one substance. Philosophical Studies, 145(1), 131–148.

  122. Schaffer, J. (2013). The action of the whole. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 87(1), 67–87.

  123. Sellars, W. (1963). Philosophy and the scientific image of man. In Empiricism and the philosophy of mind (pp. 1–40). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd.

  124. Simpson, W. M. R., Koons, R. C., & Teh, N. J. (Eds.). (2017). Neo-Aristotelian perspectives on contemporary science. New York: Routledge.

  125. Smart, B. T. H., & Thébault, K. P. Y. (2015). Dispositions and the principle of least action revisited. Analysis, 75(3), 386–395.

  126. Smith, W. (1999). From Schrödinger’s cat to Thomistic ontology. The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review, 63(1), 49–63.

  127. Steinhardt, P. J. (2011). The inflation debate: Is the theory at the heart of modern cosmology deeply flawed? Scientific American, 304(4), 36–43.

  128. Stoeger, W. R., Ellis, G. F. R., & Kirchner, U. (2004). Multiverses and cosmology: Philosophical issues. http://arxiv.org/abs/astro-ph/0407329. Accessed March 3, 2018.

  129. Tahko, T. E. (2017). Disentangling nature’s joints. In W. M. R. Simpson, R. C. Koons & N. J. Teh (Eds.), Neo-Aristotelian perspectives on contemporary science (pp. 147–166). New York: Routledge.

  130. Tegmark, M. (2003). Parallel universes. Scientific American, 288(5), 40–51.

  131. Thomasson, A. L. (2007). Ordinary objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  132. Tolman, R. C. (1987). Relativity, thermodynamics, and cosmology. New York: Dover Publications.

  133. Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(4), 667–698.

  134. Unger, R. M., & Smolin, L. (2014). The singular universe and the reality of time: A proposal in natural philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  135. van Brakel, J. (2013). Philosophy of chemistry: Between the manifest and the scientific image (reprint ed.). Leuven: Leuven University Press.

  136. von Weizsäcker, C. F. (2014). Carl Friedrich von Weizsäcker: Major texts in philosophy (M. Drieschner, Ed.). Cham: Springer.

  137. Wallace, W. A. (1979). From a realist point of view: Essays on the philosophy of science. Washington, DC: University Press of America.

  138. Wallace, W. A. (1996). The modeling of nature: Philosophy of science and philosophy of nature in synthesis. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.

  139. Wallace, D. (2012). The emergent multiverse: quantum theory according to the Everett interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  140. White, M. J. (1992). The continuous and the discrete: Ancient physical theories from a contemporary perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  141. Whitrow, G. J. (1959). Structure and evolution of the universe: An introduction to cosmology (2nd ed.). New York: Harper & Row.

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper was produced as part of the author’s postdoctoral research project, supported by a grant from CONICYT, FONDECYT, Postdoctoral Proj. No. 3170446. The author gratefully acknowledges this financial support and the faculty and staff of his home institution, Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile, Instituto de Filosofía. Research for this paper was also conducted at the University of Notre Dame, as a guest of the John J. Reilly Center for Science, Technology and Values and the Jacques Maritain Center, and the author thanks Anjan Chakravartty, John O’Callaghan, and their staff for their support and hospitality during that visit. The two anonymous reviewers also receive the author’s thanks for their substantive and insightful comments, which have helped to improve the paper tremendously. The author also gives thanks to many others for their comments, conversations, and suggestions for this paper and its topics, while retaining all blame for remaining errors: José Tomás Alvarado, Oscar Leon, Fr. Phillip Neri Reese OP, Martin Beers, Fr. Thomas Davenport OP, Ryan Shea, Nicholas Teh, Anjan Chakravartty, Jack Cahalan, Matthew Minerd, Marco Stango, Andrew Seeley, Marina Brungardt, and the attendees of the 2017 IIo Congreso Latinoamericano de Filosofía Científica and the 2017 Meeting of the American Catholic Philosophical Association for their comments on predecessor versions of this paper. Finally, in thanks for her insights into cosmology that have helped his own thinking, the author dedicates this paper to Dr. Carol Day.

Author information

Correspondence to John G. Brungardt.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

About this article

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brungardt, J.G. World enough and form: why cosmology needs hylomorphism. Synthese (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02112-0

Download citation

Keywords

  • Hylomorphism
  • Philosophy of cosmology
  • Universe
  • Laws
  • Meta-law dilemma